Architecture and Philosophy Architecture Technology Culture 6 Editors Klaus Benesch (University of Munich, Germany) Jeffrey L. Meikle (University of Texas at Austin, USA) David E. Nye (University of Southern Denmark, Denmark) Miles Orvell (Temple University, Philadelphia, USA) Editorial Address: Prof. Dr. Klaus Benesch Department of English/American Studies University of Munich Schelling strasse 3/VG 80799 Munich Architecture and Philosophy New Perspectives on the Work of Arakawa & Madeline Gins Jean-Jacques Lecercle and Françoise Kral Amsterdam - New York, NY 2010 In memory of Arakawa – who crossed borders between continents, disciplines, and, ultimately, life and death itself. All illustrations, including the cover illustration: © Arakawa and Gins/Reversible Destiny Foundation. Cover design: Pier Post The paper on which this book is printed meets the requirements of “ISO 9706: 1994, Information and documentation - Paper for documents - Requirements for permanence.” ISBN: 978-90-420-3189-0 E-Book ISBN: 978-90-420-3190-6 © Editions Rodopi B.V., Amsterdam - New York, NY 2010 Printed in The Netherlands Contents Jean-Jacques Lecercle and Françoise Kral Preface........................................................................................... 7 Jean-Jacques Lecercle Gins and Arakawa, or The Passage to Materialism.................................. 17 Jed Rasula Endless House—Architectural Body.......................................................... 37 Alan Prohm Architecture and Poetic Efficacy: Architectural Poetics .................................................................................. 53 Fionn C. Bennett “Autopoietic Event Matrices” in Architecture and in Literature: Wordsworth Talks to Arakawa and Gins ................................................... 75 Joshua Schuster How Architecture Became Biotopian: From Meta-Biology to Causal Networks in Arakawa and Gins’ Architectural Body ................................ 95 Françoise Kral Architectural Body as Generative Utopia? ............................................... 113 Chris L. Smith Preceding an Architectural Body .............................................................. 125 Jondi Keane A Bioscleave Report: Constructing the Perceiver ..................................... 143 Ronald Shusterman Leafing Through a Universe: Architectural Bodies and Fictional Worlds 169 6 Simone Rinzler Arakawa and Gins’s Architectural Body: a Transgeneric Manifesto .......................................................................... 189 Linda Pillière “No Mere Play on Words.” A stylistic Analysis of Architectural Body ..................................................................................... 207 Authors ...................................................................................................... 223 Appendix ................................................................................................... 225 Preface Jean-Jacques Lecercle and Françoise Kral It is trivially true that philosophy has always attempted to read architecture—to find a space for it in a general theory of aesthetics, to account for it within a general theory of spatial experience, to assess its contribution to the understanding of our daily life. And it is equally true, and equally trivial, that philosophy has had to acknowledge that architecture thinks, that is, produces its own concepts, and that such concepts, in return, may help to read the philosophy that claims to read architecture. This reciprocal relationship, which is not a case of fusion, may be thought in the philosophical language of Gilles Deleuze, as the creation of a disjunctive synthesis, whereby the two heterogeneous series of philosophy and architecture form an assem- blage, without losing their heterogeneity: such assemblage is rich with the promise of lines of flight, deterritorializations and the emergence of various haeccities. The usual view of the relationship between philosophy and architecture, there lies its triviality, still reasons in terms of two independent discipline s, that is two independent series, which are somehow assembled, at a certain stage of their development, to produce new mixtures. But what if the two series are entwined from the very beginning, what if the architect is, at the same time and indissolubly, a philosopher (and also, why not, an artist and a linguist)? Such a situation will probably induce in the professional philosopher corporative reactions of the “keep off the grass variety”: there is a specificity of philosophy, and an architect cannot be a true philosopher, only a kind of philosophical fou littéraire. One of the weaknesses of the Sokal hoax, and its attempted theorizing by Sokal and Bricmont, is that when they left the safe territory of their specialism, theoretical physics, to venture into philosophy, their incompetence became painfully obvious. 8 Jean-Jacques Lecercle and Françoise Kral But such dismissal by the specialist is not so easy to achieve in the case of Arakawa and Gins, and it will take the combined efforts of an array of specialists of several disciplines, philosophers, linguists and literary critics, to resist their philosophical onslaught—this is indeed what this book is about. Arakawa and Gins are undoubtedly architects, even if both first experimented with other artistic fields, where their work also gained recognition, before turning to architecture: Arakawa’s relationship to Duchamp is well-known, and his paintings have been celebrated by Lyotard; as for Madeline Gins, she is a name among avant-garde writers, in a scene dominated by the school of language poets. Their early works, whether it be Arakawa’s abstract paintings or Madeline Gins’ poetry show signs of the themes that were later to be central to their architectural project. Arakawa’s move away from monochrome painting in the 1960s to a growing interest in and research into the three dimensions in the 1980s can be read as a sign of a growing interest in architectural structures, in particular those reflecting on the position of the subject in relation to the painting. As for Madeline Gins, her reflection on the temporality of writing in her poems—in which fragments, erased and written over suggest the palimpsestic nature of art and its development through time—can be read as the first step towards a reflection on temporality which underlies a work such as Architectural Body. The block of flats they erected in Tokyo was recently given half a page in the French newspaper Le Monde (the irony of it, for whoever is aware of their insistence on reversible destiny, was that the a rticle dealt with their architectural work as an attempted solution to the problems of an aging population in Japanese cities). Since the publication of Architectural Body, we have discov- ered, and had to acknowledge, that they are genuine philosophers, that they have produced a body of work that cannot be dismissed as the feeble effort of mere amateurs. There is an undeniable grandeur in Architectural Body, the grandeur of the archetypal philosophical gesture that abandons doxa to indulge in paradox, the outcome of which is the production of philosophical truths, or rather, since De- leuze has taught us that such is the object of philosophy, the creation of new concepts, with duly picturesque names such as landing sites, bioscleave or organism that persons: the result of this work of Preface 9 philosophical creation is nothing short of a new mapping of our experience and of the construction of our lived world. Such weaving together of heterogeneous series, this disjunctive synthesis of theories of space, of perception, of language and of literature needs, in order to be read, that is to be understood and put to work in various fields, the collaborative assessment of specialists of each of those disciplines: you will find in this volume essays by philosophers of language and of literature, specialists in linguistic pragmatics and enunciation theory, literary critics and poeticians, as well as theorists of architecture. Architectural poetics, autopoetic event matrices, biotopian architecture, architecture as generative uto- pia, architecture and postmodernist literary experiments, transgeneric manifestoes, down to the materialism of space on which Arakawa and Gins’s philosophy might be based: the volume seeks to do justice to the sheer scope and diversity of their intervention in many fields. Since all this is a little abstract, let me take three examples, in three different fields. There is a sense in which the philosophy of Arakawa and Gins is not only materialist, but Deleuzian: their interest in the paradoxes of sense, rather than meaning (the fixed meaning of doxa) echoes the Deleuze of Logic of Sense; their organism that persons seeks to do the philosophical work the classical concept of subject (as centre of consciousness and of agency) is no longer able to do in our post-modern conjuncture, and echoes of the Deleuzian concepts of haeccity and collective assemblage of enunciation can be perceived in their work. As indeed Artaud’s body without organs, of which Deleuze and Gu attari make systematic philosophical use, is not far from the processual concept of the organism that persons (the body without organs does not deny the existence of organs and organisms, it seeks to make them the results of the freezing of a process of becoming, even as the organism that persons emerges in a process of tentativeness). We understand, when we read Arakawa and Gins, why Deleuze considered architecture as “the first among the arts,” and why his work is obsessively concerned with rhizomatic connections between the concepts of philosophy and the percepts and affects of art: of such connections is the work of Arakawa and Gins made. There is also a sense in which their conception of language (and their version of architecture can always be phrased in terms of language, as is manifest in the famous phrase, “the tense of
Description: