ebook img

Aquinas’ Proofs for God’s Existence: St. Thomas Aquinas on: “The Per Accidens Necessarily Implies the Per Se” PDF

207 Pages·1973·12.82 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Aquinas’ Proofs for God’s Existence: St. Thomas Aquinas on: “The Per Accidens Necessarily Implies the Per Se”

AQUINAS' PROOFS FOR GOD'S EXISTENCE AQUINAS' PROOFS FOR GOD'S EXISTENCE ST. THOMAS AQUINAS ON: "THE PER ACCIDENS NECESSARILY IMPLIES THE PER SE" by DENNIS BONNETTE, Ph.D . • MARTINUS NI]HOFF /THE HAGUE/ 1972 © I972 by Martinus Nijhoff. The Hague. Netherlands All rights reserved. including the right to translate or to reproduce this book or parts thereof in any form ISBN-13: 978-90-247-1303-5 e-ISBN-13: 978-94-010-2380-1 DOl. 10.1007/978-94-010-2380-1 PREFACE The purpose of this study is to investigate the legitimacy of the principle, "The per accidens necessarily implies the per se," as it is found in the writings of St. Thomas Aquinas. Special emphasis will be placed upon the function of this principle in the proofs for God's existence. The relevance of the principle in this latter context can be seen at once when it is observed that it is the key to the solution of the well known "prob lem of infinite regress." The investigation of the principle in question will be divided into two Parts. A preliminary examination of the function of the principle will be made in Part I: Domains Other Than That of Creature-God. The domains to be considered in this Part are those of accident-substance, change, and knowledge. Employing what is learned of the function of the principle in these areas of application, Part II: The Domain of Creature-God will analyze the role of the principle in the proofs for God's existence. This latter Part will constitute the greater portion of the book, since the domain of creatures in their relation to God is the most significant application of the principle in the writings of St. Thomas. In the course of this investigation, relevant analyses by St. Thomas' commentators - both classical and contemporary - will be considered. Finally, in light of the insights offered by St. Thomas and his commen tators, an attempt will be made to show why St. Thomas considers that "The per accidens necessarily implies the per se," is a genuinely meta physical principle - universal and necessary in its application. I am indebted to Professor Joseph Bobik of the University of Notre Dame for the original idea of the topic to be investigated. More importantly, I wish to express my deepest appreciation to Dr. Bobik for his tireless and incisive criticism of my work. Only through his fruitful suggestions - flowing from his profound grasp of the thought VI PREFACE of St. Thomas - has this study been brought to completion. Whatever of value may be found herein must be ascribed to Dr. Bobik's inspi ration and guidance. Wherever there is found failure, I freely admit it as my own. Further, I am personally indebted to my entire family for the sym pathy, patience, and encouragement so vitally needed by anyone who attempts a project of this sort. Most of all, this debt is owed to my wife, Lois - to whom, in loving appreciation, I dedicate this book. DENNIS BONNETTE Niagara University Lewiston, New York ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS The author wishes to thank sincerely and Random House Inc. for permission to quote from Etienne Gilson's Christian Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas (translated by L. K. Shook), TABLE OF CONTENTS Preface v Introduction I The Nature and Limits of the Inquiry - The Central Contexts to be Analysed PART I DOMAINS OTHER THAN THAT OF CREATURE-GOD CHAPTER I. THE DOMAIN OF ACCIDENT-SUBSTANCE 9 Accident Implies Substance - A Self-Evident Principle - Classical Modem Objections are Irrelevant - How Accidents Depend on Substance - A More Profound Reason CHAPTER II. THE DOMAIN OF CHANGE 20 The Problem of Change - A Difficulty - The Per Accidens in Change Necessarily Requires the Per Se CHAPTER III. THE DOMAIN OF KNOWLEDGE Sense Knowledge - The First and Second Acts of the Mind - The Third Act of the Mind - The Necessity of a Per Se - The Nature of the Scientific Syllogism - A Possible Confusion - The Argument - A Clarification - New Definitions PART II THE DOMAIN OF CREATURE-GOD INTRODUCTION: THE CAUSE OF PER ACCIDENS BEING 53 CHAPTER I. THE WAY OF THE DE ENTE ET ESSENTIA 56 The Way - Essence and Existence - The Argument Itself - A Further Argument VIII TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER II. APROPOS OF THE QUINQUE VIAE IN GENERAL 69 The Ways - The Problem of Infinite Multitude - Proper Causality CHAPTER III. THE PRIMA VIA 80 The Way - The Principle in Question - The Arguments - Sylvester of Ferrara - A Second Argument - A Further Argument - Con temporary Comment CHAPTER IV. THE SECUNDA VIA 105 The Way - Efficient Causality - The Argument - The Commen tary on the Metaphysics - The Commentators - Contemporary Comment - Conclusions on Efficient Causality CHAPTER V. THE TERTIA VIA 127 The Way - The Argument - The Latter Part of the Proof CHAPTER VI. THE QUARTA VIA 140 The Way - The Argument - The Principle in Question - Parti cipation and Analogy - Proof from St. Thomas CHAPTER VII. THE QUINTA VIA 157 The Way - Finality in St. Thomas - Chance - An Intelligent Orderer - Necessity of a Per Se - The General Arguments CONCLUSION 181 Exterior Causality - The Quinque Viae - Three Categories of Application - The Principle in General-The Other Applications - A Final Comment Appendix Bibliography Index INTRODUCTION 1. THE NATURE AND LIMITS OF THE INQUIRY This book is partly historical and partly systematic. It is historical in the sense that it arises out of the writings of an historical figure, St. Thomas Aquinas. For St. Thomas holds as a necessary proposition the principle that whatever is per accidens must be reduced to that which is per se.1 And yet, although he ventures close to explicit treatment of the topic on two occasions,2 St. Thomas never offers an ex professo analysis of the principle. Such an analysis is needed. For although it is immediately clear that the per accidens or per aliud 3 necessarily requires an aliud, it is not immediately clear that this other must be, ultimately, something per se (and this especially in the context of proving God's existence). Although St. Thomas does employ the principle in question as self-evident in several of the contexts we shall investigate,4 nevertheless it will have to be determined at some later point whether such "self-evidence" depends solely on the particulars of those contexts or whether, rather, it can be established in virtue of something proper to the universal nature of the per accidens in relation to the per se. It is with respect to this problem that this study becomes systematic. And the systematic task becomes to show whether the principle at issue, as such, must function in each and every order. St. Thomas does not explicitly undertake such a task. The reason why the phrase, 1 Cf. S.T., I-II, 35, 7; De Prin. Nat., 3, n. 352; In I Phys., 14, n. 7; In I Post. Anal., 7, n. 8; 37, n. 5. See Appendix for a list of Latin editions employed for the works of St. Thomas Aquinas cited. 2 In I Post. Anal., 7 and In II Meta., 3 and 4. 3 That the term "per aliud" is frequently substituted for "per accidens" will be seen later. See below, p. 10, footnote 8. 4 See below, pp. 9-37. 2 INTRODUCTION "principle ... as such," is employed here is that there are two occasions 5 on which St. Thomas does explicitly treat a somewhat different topic, the problem of infinite regress, which when viewed from the proper perspective, illuminates the relationship of the per accidens to the per se. Although such portions of the book are termed "systematic," insofar as they do not merely elucidate the explicit arguments of St. Thomas, nonetheless, every attempt will be made to remain faithful to the thought of St. Thomas by grounding each argument in his writings and, where absolutely necessary, by building new insights in a manner which accords with these writings. Although St. Thomas frequently cites the proposition in support of an argument,6 he never explicitly defends the principle: And, as noted above, even indirect defense of the principle is offered by him on very few occasions. This explains the otherwise perhaps surprising fact that relatively few texts of St. Thomas will be quoted. In fact, since the choice of contexts to be investigated will be deliberately systematic,7 appropriate use of the selected portions dictates a limited presentation of their texts. Of course, parallel citations will be taken from parts of St. Thomas' writings which fall outside the selected sections wherever useful or illuminating. Further, the contributions of St. Thomas' commentators will be noted in those contexts to which they are applicable. And, although according to the best available information there are virtually no formal treatments of this topic by contemporary writers, the thought of these writers will be consulted when advantageous to the development of the study. As expressed earlier, the purpose of this book is to investigate the legitimacy of the principle, "The per accidens necessarily implies the per se," as it is found in the writings of St. Thomas Aquinas. Special emphasis is placed upon the function of this principle in the proofs for God's existence. The relevance of the principle in the latter context can be seen at once when it is observed that it is the key to the solution of the well known "problem of the infinite regress." 8 It is noteworthy that competent scholastic philosophers,9 in present ing the proofs for God's existence, do not succumb to the temptation to 5 Cf. In I Post. Anal., 7 and In II Meta., 3 and 4. 6 Cf. In I Phys., 14, n. 7; S.T., I-II, 35, 7; C.G., III, 52. 7 See below, pp. 4-6. 8 See below, pp. 74-75, 84-85. 9 See below, pp. 71-72. INTRODUCTION 3 reject the possibility of infinite regress out of hand by relying on St. Thomas' "argument against an infinite multitude in act." 10 For, since an infinite regress in act would constitute such an "impossible" multi tude, no infinite regress in act would be possible. But rather than rely on any such argument, these philosophers prescind from such reasoning entirely and insist that even deeper reasons require that the regress come to a First, which is God - regardless of whether the intermediate elements in the series are finite or infinite in multitude. The wisdom of contemporary writers in this regard is witnessed by the fact that it is rather debatable whether any argument against in finite regress based upon the impossibility of an infinite multitude in act can be definitively grounded in the writings of St. Thomas, since at best it must be admitted that he demonstrated some degree of vacilla tion and hesitation on the question of the possibility of an infinite multi tude in act.H It will be shown later, in the context of the quinque viae, that some other principle - indeed, the one which this book in vestigates - is employed by St. Thomas, and, that the principle involved is legitimate.12 The need for this investigation, as noted above, lies in the fact that St. Thomas does not explicitly analyze the universal function of the principle as such. The importance of this inquiry will be seen when it is shown that the principle in question is a crucial premise in other major contexts, and not only with respect to the proofs for God's existence. I t is not the proper function of this book to test the legitimacy of all of the many terms and principles of St. Thomas which may be intro duced in the development of the topic, e.g., accident, substance, form, matter, privation, etc. Nor are such concepts simply accepted on the authority of St. Thomas. Rather, since the purpose of this book is to examine the function of the principle, "The per accidens necessarily implies the per se," such terms will be accepted with the sole intention of seeing whether, given some per accidens principle such as accident, there must necessarily be some corresponding per se, such as substance. And thus, in the proofs for God's existence, the intention is not to prove the existence of any per aliud, e.g., beings in motion, caused causes, contingent beings, etc. Rather, the proper concern of this book is simply to show that, assuming some such per aliud, then something per se is necessarily required. 10 Cf. S.T., I, 7, 4. 11 See below, pp. 72-74. 12 See below, pp. 84-126.

Description:
The purpose of this study is to investigate the legitimacy of the principle, "The per accidens necessarily implies the per se," as it is found in the writings of St. Thomas Aquinas. Special emphasis will be placed upon the function of this principle in the proofs for God's existence. The relevance o
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.