ebook img

Anosognosia and the very idea of psychodynamic neuroscience by Andrew Sims BA. PDF

259 Pages·2015·2.24 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Anosognosia and the very idea of psychodynamic neuroscience by Andrew Sims BA.

Anosognosia and the very idea of psychodynamic neuroscience by Andrew Sims BA. (Hons.) BSc. Submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Deakin University September, 2014 Acknowledgments I couldn’t have finished this dissertation without the support of my parents, friends, teachers, and colleagues. Professional acknowledgments are due in particular to Russell Grigg, for his thoughtful supervision; Jim Hopkins, who introduced me to the neuropsychoanalysis group in London and the psychoanalysis unit at UCL and who was always very generous with his time and advice; Tamas Pataki, Matthew Sharpe, and Geoff Boucher, who assisted with some friendly criticism and discussion of this dissertation’s themes towards the end of writing; and Leonardo Nascimento, who is responsible for getting me interested in the historical story that makes psychodynamic neuroscience intelligible in the first place. Most of all though I would like to thank my partner Ash Reynolds, without whom I would not be writing these acknowledgments at all. Contents 0. Introduction: why psychodynamic explanation? ................................................. 1 0.1. The poverty of cognition alone ............................................................................. 1 0.2. How does cognition interact with emotion and motivation? ................................. 5 0.3. The project of psychodynamic neuroscience ........................................................ 6 0.4. The thesis ............................................................................................................... 9 0.5. The argument ....................................................................................................... 10 1. Psychodynamic explanation and the unity of science ....................................... 15 1.1. Is psychoanalysis autonomous? ........................................................................... 15 1.2. Internal meta-theory: psychoanalysis is an extension of commonsense psychology .................................................................................................................. 25 1.3. External meta-theory: the relationship of psychoanalysis to other disciplines ... 40 1.4. Concluding remarks ............................................................................................ 58 2. Psychodynamic explanation and its metapsychological commitments ........... 61 2.1. A classic example of psychodynamic explanation, and its philosophical interpretation .............................................................................................................. 64 2.2. How might AHP be psychodynamically explained? ........................................... 84 2.3. Metapsychology and the role of mechanism ....................................................... 86 2.4. Metapsychological commitments of psychodynamic explanation ...................... 90 2.5. Concluding remarks ............................................................................................ 95 3. Predictive processing and the circumstances of wish-fulfilment ..................... 97 3.1. Freud and free energy: an early attempt to mechanize wish-fulfilment .............. 99 3.2. Predictive processing and the free energy principle .......................................... 106 3.3. Psychodynamic mechanisms in the free energy view of the brain .................... 124 3.4. Concluding remarks .......................................................................................... 134 4. Drives, priors, and the opacity of wish-fulfilment ........................................... 137 4.1. What are the drives, and what do they do? ........................................................ 140 4.2. Accommodating drives within the free energy framework ............................... 165 4.3. Concluding remarks .......................................................................................... 171 5. A neuropsychodynamic theory of anosognosia for hemiplegia ..................... 173 5.1. A comprehensive overview of the phenomenon to be explained ..................... 175 5.2. Cognitivist theories of anosognosia: their merits and limitations ..................... 188 5.3. Psychodynamic theories of anosognosia: their merits and limitations ............. 195 5.4. Removing objections against a neuropsychodynamic theory of anosognosia for hemiplegia ................................................................................................................ 205 5.5. Concluding remarks .......................................................................................... 218 6. Conclusion: the very idea of psychodynamic neuroscience ........................... 220 References ............................................................................................................... 223 1 0. Introduction: why psychodynamic explanation?1 0.1. The poverty of cognition alone 0.2. How does cognition interact with emotion and motivation? 0.3. The project of psychodynamic neuroscience 0.4. The thesis 0.5. The argument 0.1. The poverty of cognition alone In some patients who suffer damage to a particular region of their right cerebral hemisphere, they suffer a peculiar malady that seems to have two components. The first component is a paralysis on the left side of the body, which often co-occurs with a neglect on that side – an inability to attend to and engage with objects in the affected part of the visual field.2 The second component is an inability to recognize these impairments, as well as a tendency to go to great lengths in order to deny them – sometimes to the point of denying ownership of the affected part of the body, or trying again and again to walk unassisted when their paralysis makes this impossible. This inability to recognize one’s symptoms does tend to subside after the acute phase of this condition, and is often replaced by a curious emotional attitude towards the affected part of the body which ranges from benign disinterest to intense hatred. The condition is sometimes called right parietal lobe syndrome, but most often all of these symptoms are assimilated to the label of “anosognosia for hemiplegia.” (AHP)3 1 I will be using both “psychoanalytic” and “psychodynamic” to denote the style of explanation which is at issue in this dissertation. The difference between these has been thought to come down to the specificity of the former in comparison to the latter; psychoanalysis involves clinical treatment five days a week along lines close to what Freud originally practiced, but psychodynamic therapies cover a wider range of different theories and methods (Cf., Shedler 2006: 9-10). The relatively small differences between psychodynamic treatments will not be relevant here, since I establish a specific view on the general structure of psychodynamic explanation in chapter two (and I am not primarily concerned with the clinical efficacy of psychodynamic treatment). 2 However, there is no necessary connection between anosognosia and neglect, and there are cases in the literature for which these are dissociated (Jekhonen et al. 2000). 3 The nosology is in fact slightly more complicated than this, since the condition is comprised of a number of symptoms that do not always occur together. The denial of paralysis itself is anosognosia for hemiplegia, the delusion that the damaged limb does not belong to the patient is somatoparaphrenia, and the existence of distorted emotional attitudes towards the deficit is 2 The impetus behind this thesis is a related set of questions about how to explain conditions like these. For example, what roles are emotion and cognition each playing in this illness, and how can we distinguish between them? In order to elucidate this query a provisional definition is in order. I am referring to the emotions both in their neuropsychological and phenomenological aspects. That means I am referring to the way that the emotion feels as well as to the physical structure (in the brain, at least) that is a necessary condition for its existence. I will, however, sometimes explicitly distinguish between these physical and phenomenological aspects. Furthermore, I include the behavioural, perceptual, and cognitive aspects that are often also taken to be constitutive of the emotion. By cognition, I mean all thought that is evaluable in terms of truth-conditions; what that means is that cognitive tokens have conceptual content – they represent the world in the same way that language represents the world.4 These initial definitions are not perfect and will become clearer over the course of the thesis, but they will do at this point. Back to the initial question: what roles are affect and cognition playing in AHP, and can we make them conceptually distinct in explanations of that illness? For example, can we eschew emotion entirely in the aetiology of the illness by understanding it as being solely caused by cognitive deficit? That kind of explanation would seek to elucidate the illness in terms of mechanisms that can no longer perform their proper function and so produce the pathological phenomena though their breakdown. One example of this explanatory strategy is that of Cutting (1978), who suggests that for many anosognosics it is in virtue of a failure to integrate information about the body into judgments about impairment – this failure being caused by the neglect – that the patient cannot recognize their deficit. anosodiaphoria if the attitude is indifference and misoplegia if the attitude is hatred. See Orfei et al. (2007) for a relatively recent review that elucidates this clinical variability in more detail. 4 This might seem like a non-standard definition of what cognition is, whereas what might seem more appropriate is mental activity that can be understood in terms of information- processing. The reason I opt for this one is that I wish to include personal-level states like delusional beliefs attributed by the clinician that may be the result of information processing but which are not themselves information-processing states in the sense meant by cognitive scientists. 3 The theory proposed by Cutting is what philosophers call a “one-factor theory” of the anosognosia. The distinction between one-factor theories and two-factor theories is one that originates in the study of delusions (e.g., Davies et al. 2001). A one-factor theory of delusion is one that explains it to be a normal cognitive response to an unusual experience brought on by some kind of sensory or cognitive deficit. In the case of AHP, a simple one-factor theory of the condition would posit that the denial of paralysis is a normal cognitive response for somebody who lacks proprioceptive information about or who cannot attend to the paralysed limb. The deficit causes an unusual experience, which causes the agent to form a false belief about the state of the body. It is, on the theory, a reasonable belief to form under the circumstances of the deficit. The only pathogenic cause that is present according to this one-factor theory of anosognosia is the deficit (for example, in the mechanisms of attention), and it is thought that this deficit alone is enough to explain the subsequent delusion in conjunction with ordinary processes of belief fixation. The flaw in single factor theories of the condition is that the neuropsychological deficit is not a sufficient condition for the illness, either descriptively or normatively. It is not descriptively sufficient because there are people who have the same cognitive deficit that do not have the anosognosia. For example, and with reference to Cutting, it has been found that neglect and anosognosia for paralysis “double-dissociate”; we can find each symptom in a patient along with an absence of the other. (e.g., Jehkonen et al. 2000) The single factor is not normatively sufficient for the delusion either. What that means is that although an unusual experience caused by deficit might give rise to a candidate belief that seems particularly salient or plausible due to that experience, it does not explain why this belief is accepted despite other evidence to the contrary; some examples of contrary evidence might be testimony from the examining doctor or nurses, or visual evidence that one’s paralysed arm is not moving. And it does not explain why the delusional belief persists as this evidence accumulates. By contrast, the “two-factor theory” of anosognosia posits a second pathological factor in the genesis and persistence of the condition. One theory 4 of this type is that of Davies, Aimola Davies and Coltheart (2005). The first factor in their theory is the neuropsychological deficit that leads to an unusual experience eliciting a false belief about the state of the body. They suggest that the second factor in the right theory of anosognosia will be a deficit in belief- evaluation processes, and that this will account for the persistence of the anosognosia. This is a theory of anosognosia that continues to explain it in terms of cognitive deficit, but that explains it in terms of two cognitive deficits (or maybe two types of deficit, since each factor may well include more than one functional deficit) that together produce the anosognosia. Now, there is a further debate about the nature of the second factor in anosognosia. More specifically, it is a debate over the nature of the second factor with respect to the distinctions between cognitive, affective, and motivational states. For example, is the anosognosic patient’s failure to update his delusional beliefs in response to contrary evidence the result of a deficit in the cognitive mechanisms that govern evaluation of belief, or does he maintain these beliefs because (say) the motivation to hold these beliefs is overpowering? Early theories of anosognosia gave a central explanatory role to motivational factors. Weinstein and Kahn (1950), for instance, hypothesized that denial of illness was a generalized defensive reaction against the negative emotion that acknowledgment of illness would cause. But theories of this kind have seriously fallen out of favour since the uptake of theories that purport to fully explain the illness in terms of cognitive deficit. One-factor or two-factor, a theory of anosognosia that relies exclusively on cognitive deficit for its explanation will just not do.5 This view will be defended more substantially against various objections in chapter five of the thesis, and I introduce it only in order to discuss the problems that motivationally-based explanations of pathology must face. But here are some 5 My claim here is not, however, that all cases of anosognosia for hemiplegia must be explained in terms of motivation and emotion. That seems pretty clearly untrue, and I suspect that there are many subsets of the clinical population with anosognosia whose illness could be explained without drawing on these factors (e.g., along lines suggested by Aimola Davies & Davies (2009)). The claim is rather that these factors (emotion and motivation) are needed to explain some cases, and therefore that we need a more general account of how it is that these factors could come to play a role in such illnesses. I am claiming that cognitive deficit accounts are insufficient to account for all cases of anosognosia on their own.

Description:
1. Psychodynamic explanation and the unity of science . Freud and free energy: an early attempt to mechanize wish-fulfilment .. 99 exclusively hermeneutic rather than causal reasoning, then one might see the testing of psychodynamic theories in an experimental setting to be premised on.
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.