ebook img

An Ontology of Art PDF

154 Pages·1989·15.216 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview An Ontology of Art

AN ONTOLOGY OF ART An Ontology of Art Gregory Currie Pal grave Macmillan ISBN 978-1-349-20040-5 ISBN 978-1-349-20038-2 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-1-349-20038-2 ©Scots Philosophical Club, 1989 Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st edition 1989 978-0-333-46076-4 All rights reserved. For information, write: Scholarly and Reference Division, St. Martin's Press, Inc., 175 Fifth Avenue, New York, N.Y. 10010 First published in the United States of America in 1989 ISBN 978-0-312-02856-5 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Currie, Gregory. An ontology of art/Gregory Currie. p. em. Bibliography: p. Includes index. ISBN 978-0-312-02856-5 1. Art-Philosophy. I. Title. N70.C89 1989 701-dcl9 88--38728 CIP For Penny Contents Preface x Acknowledgements xii 1 Introduction 1 1. The project 1 2. Types and tokens 3 3. A theory to be refuted 4 4. Art works as action types 7 5. The multiplicity of instances 8 6. Some logical considerations 8 7. The problem of forgery 10 8. Ontology and appreciation 11 9. Kinds of works 13 10. Autographidallographic 14 11. A disclaimer 15 2 Empiricism 17 1. What is empiricism? 17 2. Empiricism and supervenience 18 3. Aesthetic properties 25 4. Why 'empiricism'? 26 5. Empiricism and the IMH 27 6. A first argument against empiricism 28 7. How to relativise aesthetic properties 31 8. Moving further away from empiricism 34 9. Aesthetic and art-historical properties 40 vii viii Contents 10. A conclusion about aesthetic value 41 II. Contextual dependence in art and science 44 3 Art Works as Action Types 46 I. Introduction 46 2. The structural account of the work 46 3. Musical works and performance means 49 4. An objection to the structural view 50 5. Correct and incorrect instances of a work 53 6. Works as norm kinds 55 7. Works as created 56 8. Works as indicated structures 57 9. Are works created? 61 10. Some constraints on theory 64 II. Works as action types 66 12. A question about heuristics 71 13. Referential properties 73 14. Some reflections on the theory 74 15. The problem of pictures 78 16. Supervenience again 79 17. Transworld identification of works 80 4 Authenticity 85 I. Preliminaries 85 2. Is the IMH revisionary? 85 3. An important difference between visual and non- visual arts 89 4. The intentional fallacy 91 5. Anti-empiricism and the IMH 92 Contents ix 6. The artist's relation to the work 96 7. Counterfactual dependence 98 8. Historical uniqueness 102 9. The problem of architecture 104 10. Forgeries and reproductions 105 11. Goodman's project 108 12. Looking 109 13. Looking and aesthetic discrimination 111 14. Forgery again 115 15. Looking revisited 117 16. Works and their instances 120 17. The problem of prints 124 18. Autographic!allographic again 124 19. Embodiment 125 20. Conclusions 127 Notes 130 References 135 Index 139 Preface Recent work in aesthetics displays a tendency to regard an art work's history, particularly the circumstances of its production, as bearing on its aesthetic qualities. There is less talk now of an 'intentional fallacy', and the claim that aesthetic appreciation can be isolated from the work's historical context is regarded with some scepticism. Along with this tendency there is discernible an attempt to re-evaluate old answers to the question, 'What is a work of art?', and to go beyond them to something more in keeping with an appreciation of the work's historical dimension. But recent answers to this question fail, I think, to give this historical dimension its proper role. Ontology has failed to keep pace with epistemology in this area. My aim is to bring about a closer connection between the two. The structure of my argument is as follows. In Chapter 1 I state my thesis and explain some of the background to it. Reduced to a slogan that thesis is this: all art works belong to the same ontological kind - action types. And all art works, including those in such apparently singular arts as painting and sculpture (where it is normal to identify the work with a unique object) may have many instances with a status equal to that of the 'authentic' instance. In Chapter 2 I try to motivate my account of art works by developing a theory about the range of features of a work that may be relevant to its appreciation. In Chapter 3 I use this account to motivate the thesis that art works are action types. In Chapter 4 I turn to the question of whether all kinds of works of art are capable of multiple instantiation. In this book I have tried to combine systematic argument, some of it polemical, with accessibility to students who are beginning to study the philosophy of art. I would like the book to be viewed both as a contribution to research and as an introduction, though not an impartial one, to some central topics in aesthetics. But these aims are not easy to reconcile, and there are probably times when the text will be tedious to the specialist and less than wholly clear to the student. In my defence I say to the specialist that it is worth while discussing these issues in a context that presupposes a minimum of philosophical background, since background x Preface xi assumptions often turn out to be highly questionable. And to the student I say that the best way to learn philosophy is to embrace controversy from the first, rather than to begin with a judicious and impartial summing up of the alternatives. It would have been possible to write a much longer book on this subject. At various points it was tempting to look at the history of aesthetic writing for guidance, to flesh out the analytical points with a closer study of examples from the history of art, to consider what further responses might be made to my arguments. But it seems to me that there is value in dealing with the issue in a way that will facilitate a broad overview of the whole position. Too often the core of a philosophical argument is obscured by a wealth of detail and the pursuit of alternative strategies. I hope that this book will give a sharper focus to what is currently a rather diffuse debate; I do not expect that it will reduce the opposition to silence. Finally, I should like to mention here the appearance of a work that suggests a growing interest among art historians with the methodology of their subject. Michael Baxandall's Patterns of In ten tion (Yale University Press, 1985) provides a number of case studies in the analysis of what I call here the 'heuristic' of a work. I suggest that Chapters 2 and 3 of my book provide something like the explanatory framework towards which Baxandall is moving. GREGORY CURRIE

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.