ebook img

An Atheistic Critique of Christian Apologetics PDF

24 Pages·2015·0.6 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview An Atheistic Critique of Christian Apologetics

Epistemology and Ethics: An Atheistic Critique of Christian Apologetics By W. J. Whitman Christianity was historically useful. Christianity is relatively functionally isomorphic to the truth, which made it vitally useful as a historical movement. Prior to discoveries made in the 19th century, the only logical alternative to religion was nihilism. Nihilism is not a philosophy that one can live by. Religion supplied an alternative to nihilism for centuries. As such, religion was basically necessary for the survival of the human species. Religion has many positive aspects. Christianity in particular is, in my opinion, among the most rational and useful of all the world religions. Nevertheless, Christians do have certain beliefs that I regard as dangerous. The Roman Catholic is bound to support statism and oppose free markets, simply because there are papal encyclicals that teach the virtues of government intervention. Whenever the Roman Catholic approaches the questions of politics and economics, he is bound by his faith to look at it through the lens of official Catholic dogma. He cannot, as a Catholic, look at economics as a mere social science, apply logic to it, and arrive at the most rational conclusion if the most rational conclusion does not coincide with Catholic dogma. The Pope is the sole authority for the Catholic. Similarly, Calvinists and fundamentalists suppose that the Bible is the sole authority. Consequently, some of them have concluded that biblical law or theonomy should be the basis of all modern law—and some of these people advocate bringing back execution as the punishment for adultery, prostitution, and “sodomy.”1 It is interesting to note that they do not apply biblical law without considerable cherry picking. They overlook the fact that Jesus identified pornography with adultery and recommended that you gouge your own eye out if you look at a woman lustfully, cut your hand off if you are tempted to masturbate, and castrate yourself to prevent temptation if you can bear it.2 The existence of dangerous sectarian ideologies that seek to 1 Cf. R. J. Rushdoony, Gary North, Gary DeMar, Greg Bahnsen, etc. 2 Cf. Matthew 5:27-30; 19:12 influence secular politics, in my opinion, justifies this attempt at refuting the Christian worldview. The most powerful arguments for religion are of an abductive nature. There are three sorts of logical processes: deduction, induction, and abduction. Deduction is merely observational and descriptive. Deductive reasoning is based on observing phenomena and describing what has happened. Inductive reasoning is a processes whereby one infers general rules from repeated observations. Abductive reasoning is a process whereby one forms an explanatory hypothesis to explain phenomena that one has observed. The really weighty arguments for Christianity are those abductive logical arguments that come from Cornelius van Til, C. S. Lewis, and G. K. Chesterton. There are many versions of the argument, but they all reduce down to this: everything about the universe that we live in makes sense if we presuppose the truth of Christianity, but makes no sense at all if we assume that any alternative religion or worldview is true. Christianity, therefore, can be looked at as a hypothesis that was proposed as a way of explaining existing evidence. The atheist and the skeptic tend to just brush off this argument as nonsense. However, when you unpack this argument and examine it closely, you will find that there really is something to this argument. It is a weighty argument for a reason. This argument has historically been quite powerful. Prior to mid-way through the 19th century, Western civilization had not discovered any viable alternative to Christianity. Christianity assumes that there is an Absolute Rationality behind the universe, a divine and personal Being, who has designed the world in which we live. The world was created and organized by an all-powerful entity. The universe is not random and chaotic, but functions in a highly rational, harmonious, and orderly fashion. There is a uniformity of the laws of nature because God has created natural laws to govern how the universe acts. Humans were created by God. Our bodies were designed to function the way that they do. He designed our brains and minds to function in a particular way, so as to allow for true rationality. He designed our eyes in a way that facilitates accurate visual perception. He designed our ears in a way that facilitates accurate auditory perception. He created us and knows what is best for us. He knows what we must do to achieve our own ultimate happiness. Consequently, He has given us a divine law and has revealed it to us in written form (theonomy or biblical law) and has “inscribed it in our hearts,” so that we can know it through intuition (natural law). As you can see, the Christian worldview explains the world we live in—it supplies us with a coherent epistemology (theory of knowledge) and a coherent ethic (theory of right conduct or morality). The presuppositionalists, following Cornelius van Til, argue that this worldview is the only one that can explain the universe in which we live and provide a framework that allows us to go about living rationally and sanely in this world. The presuppositionalist brings up the problem of induction, which was raised by David Hume. Inductive reasoning makes inferences from repeated observations. For instance, we observe that objects keep falling every time that they are dropped, so inductive reasoning leads us to the conclusion that there must be some general rule or natural law that dictates that objects must behave this way. Thus, we arrive at the law of gravity. Hume pointed out that this method of reasoning is actually invalid— it is logically a non sequitur, it does not follow from the fact that we have seen tons of objects fall to the ground that objects must necessarily always act that way. The presuppositionalist says, “Now, let’s compare my Christian worldview to your atheistic worldview. Upon Christian presuppositions, it makes perfect sense that there would be a uniformity of natural laws because God has designed the universe to function just so. Yet, upon your assumptions—assuming that the universe was not designed by a rational being, but came about through random chance and arose basically from chaos—, we have absolutely no reason to suppose that there would be any uniform laws governing natural processes.” Thus, Cornelius van Til and the presuppositionalists conclude, “There is no intelligibility in any phenomena of the universe without the presupposition of God’s all-encompassing plan.”3 Then there is the evolutionary argument against naturalism, popularized by Alvin Plantinga, but which was better 3 Cornelius van Til, An Introduction to Systematic Theology, Chapter 9 espoused by C. S. Lewis. If we assume that human beings came about entirely through random natural processes, then we have absolutely no reason to trust our own sensory perceptions and cognitive faculties. The Christian trusts his senses and his mind because he assumes that they were designed by a benevolent and rational God. However, the naturalistic atheist can make no such assumption. The logical structure of the human brain, upon atheistic assumptions, is really just the result of natural chemical reactions and colliding atomic particles inside the human skull. Why should I assume that the collision of particles and chemicals within the body should produce accurate perceptions, accurate logical deductions, and a viable structure of mind? Isn’t it much more likely that any conscious perceptions and thoughts produced by such processes would result in inaccurate perceptions, since the processes are random and are not being guided by any rational design? Why would evolution ever have produced a creature with accurate knowledge of the world around it? Natural selection would select individuals with characteristics that facilitate survival, but it would not necessarily select individuals with accurate perceptions and sound minds. Another argument is the argument from universal morality, which was also brilliantly espoused by C. S. Lewis. All men share some basic ethical principles. We assume that some things are right and other things are wrong. If somebody does something that is “mean” and we dislike it, we may say, “Hey, that’s not fair.” If someone takes our spot at a table, we may object, “That’s my spot. I was there first.” We are assuming that there are some general rules of fair play that we all agree on—that the person who is not being fair is also in agreement with us on these principles of fairness. The person who took our spot may argue, “But you left the spot, so you have given it up,” but she will hardly ever say, “To hell with your morality!”4 She will not dismiss the code of conduct altogether. On the contrary, she will try to claim the moral high ground. In actuality, we both believe that there are some general rules of fairness, justice, or morality that are, at least for humankind, universally applicable. Classical theologians, like Thomas Aquinas, referred to these rules as the 4 Cf. C. S. Lewis, Mere Christianity, Chapter 1 natural law. There is a universal law; and a universal law presupposes a universal lawmaker. These laws were given to us by God, inscribed upon our hearts, and are the basis of our ethical codes. Furthermore, we may add to these arguments the necessity of comprehensive knowledge argument. Cornelius van Til has argued that it is necessary for comprehensive knowledge to exist somewhere in order for real knowledge to exist anywhere.5 Humans used to think that the world was flat, but new discoveries have disproven that theory. The discovery of new facts can falsify things that we once thought that we “knew” to be true. We used to “know” that the world is flat, but new facts have falsified that theory. Man is finite, so he cannot know everything that there is to know. Man cannot have comprehensive knowledge of all the facts. This is very dangerous for the epistemologist! Every little fact that man does not know about could potentially falsify everything that he thinks that he “knows.” But, according to Van Til, comprehensive knowledge actually does exist. Comprehensive knowledge does exist in the mind of God. Human knowledge is derivative of divine knowledge. We can have relative knowledge of the universe because God has absolute knowledge. God protects us from the possibility of the falsification of our knowledge by the facts that we are unaware of. Finally, there is Cornelius van Til’s one-many argument. From times immemorial, philosophers have been wrestling with the problem of the one and the many (or of the general and the particular). There is a general category of trees, then there are particular trees. There is a general category of cats, and then there are particular cats. Do we call a tree “a tree” because we see it and perceive that it fits neatly into the category of trees? or, do we generalize from the many different trees and then create a category in our minds so that we can classify them? Which is logically prior, the general category or the particular instance? Which is ultimate, the one (general) or the many (particular)? Philosophers have answered this in various ways. Most of their answers have been unsatisfactory. Yet, this is quite an important question. Human knowledge rests upon compare-and-contrast analyses. Whenever we discover something 5 Cf. James Anderson, If Knowledge Then God new, we compare it to similar objects and contrast it against objects that differ from it. We gain an understanding of the new object through this compare-and-contrast analysis. We must have both the comparison and the contrast together in order to learn anything. Epistemology needs both the general and the particular to be equally real. Cornelius van Til supplies us with an interesting solution to the one-many problem. He suggest the equal ultimacy of the one and the many. Van Til points out that the Christian doctrine of the Trinity supplies a perfect solution. In the ontological Trinity, the one and the many are equally ultimate: God is simultaneously one and three. There are three particular persons within the one essence of the Godhead. So, it is suggested that God came to knowledge through an internal compare-and-contrast analysis of His own being: prior to the creation, God contemplated the Triune nature of His own being.6 This ties in to the necessity of comprehensive knowledge argument because God could not possibly have arrived at comprehensive knowledge if He had not been simultaneously one and many. Prior to creation, God existed all alone, in a void. There was nothing outside of Himself against which He could have made any contrasting analysis. Without the possibility of a compare-and-contrast analysis, God could never have had any knowledge of Himself apart from creation. This explains the importance of the Trinitarian conception of God for Christian epistemology. God created the world with the knowledge that He had gained through His own internal compare- and-contrast analysis. His self-analysis led to His thinking in a one- many fashion, and the relative categories of the one and the many in the created world correspond to eternal categories within the mind of God, which in turn depend upon the eternal categories of the one and the many within the ontological Trinity as their ultimate foundation. Cornelius van Til follows St. Augustine in asserting that the general categories that we use to classify things correspond to ideal forms in the mind of God. There is an ideal form of tree-ness in 6 However, since God exists in eternity, outside space-time, we are speaking by way of analogy when we say that God “came to knowledge.” In reality, God’s self-analysis was not a temporal process. God eternally knows Himself through an eternal compare-and-contrast analysis of the categories of the one (essence) and the many (persons) within the ontological Trinity. God’s mind, and a tree is “a tree” insofar as it corresponds to that form. There is an ideal form of human-ness within the mind of God, and humans are “humans” insofar as they correspond to God’s pre- defined concept of humankind. When we classify things into categories, according to Van Til, we are simply “thinking God’s thoughts after Him.” We are able to classify all of these things because God has created the categories for us. When we apply logic to the things that we see, and attempt to understand them and describe them, we are able to do so because God has already rationalized the world for us—we are not rationalizing the world for the first time. Up to this point, I have tried to just describe Christian dogma and explain the rationale for Christian belief. I hope that I have been clear and accurate in my representation of the Christian position. As a former believer, I think that I have accurately represented the Christian position. I will, however, ignore those points of Christian doctrine where there is considerable disagreement among believers. I think that the above is a decent summary of the essence of Christian teaching. From this point on, I will be making the case against Christianity. Christianity supplies a worldview that makes sense of the world. That is the main argument for Christianity; so, what if I can posit some other worldview that makes equal sense of everything? Wouldn’t that undermine Van Til’s contention that Christianity is a necessary presupposition? Well, I’m pretty sure I can come up with another worldview that can supply an equally coherent explanation. And I don’t have to look very far. For instance, you can look to Hindu philosophy for an alternative worldview that explains all the same things. The universe is really all an extension of the being of Bhagavan, Vishnu/God. The universe is the cosmic body of Vishnu. Everything that exists is part of God, but at the highest level—at the level of cosmic consciousness—Bhagavan is a unified whole. Each man and animal in this world is a manifestation, a little incarnation, of the deity. God is one and many. The cosmic mind of Vishnu has guided everything in the universe so that things happen in a certain way, creating a uniformity of nature. Vishnu created our bodies so that we, as little sparks of Him, might inhabit them; thus, the body is designed so that its eyes can see and its mind can think rationally. All living entities are expansions of the being of Bhagavan, containing the Paramatma (the fullness of the Godhead) within their souls. When we become enlightened, we realize that all men are really just part of the same universal being. We realize that the distinction between me and you—between the self and the other—is false. Consequently, it is in our own rational self-interest for us to not harm other people because hurting other people is actually hurting us too because there isn’t actually a difference between “us” and “them.” It is quite easy to see how Hinduism can explain all the same things that Christianity does. Christianity is not the only worldview that can be “proven” using the abductive logic of the Christian apologists. Most religions have solutions to all of these epistemological and ethical problems. Throughout history, philosophers have always discussed the same problems, and it is no surprise that religious philosophers have independently developed basically functionally isomorphic worldviews (i.e. perspectives that literally contradict each other but nevertheless lead to similar logical conclusions if they are acted upon). Now, this little exercise in comparative religion was a mere parenthetical gloss. It was just something to get you thinking. I do not mean to propose some other religious worldview as an alternative. I simply wanted to point out that all of the arguments for Christianity are equally valid arguments for other non-Christian religions. This alone, I think, is a serious stumbling block for the educated and philosophical Christian. As I noted above, the Christian believes that God created natural laws and that this explains the uniformity of nature. Thus, according to the Christian apologist, the uniformity of nature itself is evidence that God exists. Bertrand Russell responded to this argument thus: “Then there is a very common argument from natural law. That was a favorite argument all through the eighteenth century, especially under the influence of Sir Isaac Newton and his cosmogony. People observed the planets going around the sun according to the law of gravitation, and they thought that God had given a behest to these planets to move in that particular fashion, and that was why they did so. That was, of course, a convenient and simple explanation that saved them the trouble of looking any further for explanations of the law of gravitation. Nowadays we explain the law of gravitation in a somewhat complicated fashion that Einstein has introduced. I do not propose to give you a lecture on the law of gravitation, as interpreted by Einstein, because that again would take some time; at any rate, you no longer have the sort of natural law that you had in the Newtonian system, where, for some reason that nobody could understand, nature behaved in a uniform fashion. We now find that a great many things we thought were natural laws are really human conventions. You know that even in the remotest depths of stellar space there are still three feet to a yard. That is, no doubt, a very remarkable fact, but you would hardly call it a law of nature. And a great many things that have been regarded as laws of nature are of that kind. On the other hand, where you can get down to any knowledge of what atoms actually do, you will find they are much less subject to law than people thought, and that the laws at which you arrive are statistical averages of just the sort that would emerge from chance. There is, as we all know, a law that if you throw dice you will get double sixes only about once in thirty-six times, and we do not regard that as evidence that the fall of the dice is regulated by design; on the contrary, if the double sixes came every time we should think that there was design. The laws of nature are of that sort as regards a great many of them. They are statistical averages such as would emerge from the laws of chance; and that makes this whole business of natural law much less impressive than it formerly was. Quite apart from that, which represents the momentary state of science that may change tomorrow, the whole idea that natural laws imply a lawgiver is due to a confusion between natural and human laws. Human laws are behests commanding you to behave a certain way, in which you may choose to behave, or you may choose not to behave; but natural laws are a description of how things do in fact behave, and being a mere description of what they in fact do, you cannot argue that there must be somebody who told them to do that, because even supposing that there were, you are then faced with the question ‘Why did God issue just those natural laws and no others?’ If you say that he did it simply from his own good pleasure, and without any reason, you then find that there is something which is not subject to law, and so your train of natural law is interrupted. If you say, as more orthodox theologians do, that in all the laws which God issues he had a reason for giving those laws rather than others—the reason, of course, being to create the best universe, although you would never think it to look at it—if there were a reason for the laws which God gave, then God himself was subject to law, and therefore you do not get any advantage by introducing God as an intermediary. You really have a law outside and anterior to the divine edicts, and God does not serve your purpose, because he is not the ultimate lawgiver. In short, this whole argument about natural law no longer has anything like the strength that it used to have.”7 The presuppositionalist would likely respond to Bertrand Russell’s argument by quoting Cornelius van Til: “On the assumption of the natural man [that is, the non-believer] logic is a timeless, impersonal principle, and facts are controlled by chance. It is by means of universal timeless principles of logic that the natural man must, on his assumptions, seek to make intelligible assertions about the world of reality or chance. But this cannot be done without falling into self-contradiction. About chance no manner of assertion can be made. In its very idea it is the irrational. And how are rational assertions to be made about the irrational? If they are to be made, then it must be because the irrational is itself wholly reduced to the rational. That is to say, if the natural man is to make any intelligible assertions about the world of ‘reality’ or ‘fact’ which, according to him, is what it is for no rational reason at all, then he must make the virtual claim of rationalizing the irrational.”8 Indeed, the presuppositionalists have a point; but the regularity upon which probability rests can be explained without the presupposition of God. As Russell hinted, the notion of God really just sidesteps the question of the uniformity of nature and the laws of nature. Why did God create those laws? “Because He wanted to create the best possible world for us.” Why did He want to do that? “Because He loves us.” Why does He love us? “Because the essence of God is love. His nature dictates that He loves us.” But now the Christian has posited some law even further back than the laws of nature. The atheist must ask: If the laws of nature need some explanation apart from the fact that they just are, then the laws of God’s nature need an explanation too. If God’s nature can be posited as just existing and 7 Bertrand Russell, Why I Am Not a Christian 8 Cornelius van Til, The Defense of the Faith, Chapter 7, Section 1

Description:
epistemology (theory of knowledge) and a coherent ethic (theory of right conduct . From times immemorial, philosophers have been wrestling with the problem of .. Is the cicada killer wasp being unethical when it stings the cicada
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.