ebook img

An Archaeology of Disbelief : The Origin of Secular Philosophy PDF

218 Pages·2018·1.06 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview An Archaeology of Disbelief : The Origin of Secular Philosophy

An Archaeology of Disbelief The Origin of Secular Philosophy Edward Jayne EDITEDBYELAINEANDERSONJAYNE HamiltonBooks Lanham•Boulder•NewYork•Toronto•Plymouth,UK Copyright©2018byHamiltonBooks 4501ForbesBoulevard,Suite200,Lanham,Maryland20706 HamiltonBooksAcquisitionsDepartment(301)459-3366 UnitA,WhitacreMews,26-34StannaryStreet, LondonSE114AB,UnitedKingdom Allrightsreserved PrintedintheUnitedStatesofAmerica BritishLibraryCataloguinginPublicationInformationAvailable LibraryofCongressControlNumber:2017955105 ISBN:978-0-7618-6966-5(cloth:alk.paper)—ISBN:978-0-7618-6967-2(electronic) TMThepaperusedinthispublicationmeetstheminimumrequirementsofAmerican NationalStandardforInformationSciencesPermanenceofPaperforPrintedLibrary Materials,ANSI/NISOZ39.48-1992. ToElaine Withoutherhelpthisbookwouldnothavebeenpossible Contents Preface vii I. ix II. xi Introduction xiii I.AnEconomicExplanation xiv II.LossofTextualEvidence xv III.FiveSecularistsWhoSurvived xvii 1 ThePre-SocraticPhilosophers 1 I.Thales(CA.624-546BC) 2 II.Anaximander(CA.610–546BC) 4 III.Anaximenes(CA.585-528BC) 6 IV.Xenophanes(CA.570–475BC) 7 V.PherecydesofSyros(CA.580-520BC) 9 VI.PythagorasandthePythagoreans(CA.570-495BC) 10 VII.Heraclitus(CA.540-480BC) 15 VIII.Parmenides(CA.515-450BC) 20 IX.ZenoofElea(CA.490–430BC) 22 X.MelissusofSamos(wonseabattlein441BC) 24 XI.Empedocles(CA.492–432BC) 26 XII.Anaxagoras(CA.500–428BC) 29 XIII.DiogenesofApollonia(CA.425BC) 34 XIV.Leucippus(CA.early5thcenturyBC) 36 XV.Democritus(CA.460–370BC) 40 XVI.FinalConsiderations 46 2 PlatoandtheAgeofPericles 53 I.Sophists 53 v vi Contents II.Protagoras(c.490-420BC) 56 III.Socrates(469-339BC) 57 IV.Plato(427–347BC) 59 3 EarlyAristotle(384-322BC) 67 I.ComparisonwithPlato 70 II.ChristianInterpolations 74 III.Physics 76 IV.Metaphysics 81 4 LateAristotle 87 I.DeCaelo(OnTheHeavens) 87 II.OnGenerationandCorruption 95 III.DeAnima(OntheSoul) 99 IV.NicomacheanEthics 106 V.Afterword 107 5 TheLyceumafterAristotle 111 I.Theophrastus(CA.371-287BC) 113 II.StratoofLampsacus(CA.335-287BC) 117 6 TheEpicureans 127 I.Epicurus(341-270BC) 127 II.Lucretius(CA.99-55BC) 134 7 Skepticism 147 I.Pyrrho(CA.360-270BC) 149 II.Arcesilaus(CA.316-241BC) 151 III.Carneades(214-128BC) 154 8 Cicero(106-43B.C.) 161 I.Academica 162 II.OntheNatureoftheGods 166 Epilogue 177 Notes 183 SelectiveBibliography 185 I.PrimaryTexts 185 II.SecondaryTexts 186 Index 189 Preface SocrateswasexecutedforatheisminAthens,andotherancientphilosophers such as Theophrastus and even Aristotle were confronted by the same pos- sibility. Several centuries later many libraries seem to have been destroyed by fire in order to eradicate all texts suggestive of secular philosophy, and still later medieval Christian scribes and scholars resorted to textual censor- shipwithcomparableresults.Suchextremeshaveofcoursebeenabandoned since the Renaissance, but modern classical scholarship has effectively sus- tained this dubious effort by ignoring or deemphasizing the materialist per- spective of ancient secularists such as Democritus, Strato, Carneades and evenAristotledespiteampletextualevidencetothecontrary. At the turn of the twentieth century, the eminent classicist John Burnet wentsofarastoexplainthattheprimaryachievementofearlyGreekphilos- ophers consisted of “the faith that reality is divine” in the shared “effort to satisfywhatwecallthereligiousinstinct.”1Ineffectheproposedthatancient Greek philosophy served as an early version of religion dedicated to the concept of existence as a product of one or more gods. The no less eminent scholar, W.K.C. Guthrie, apparently shared this assumption as suggested by hisreluctancetoacknowledgesecularanalysis.Hisfive-volumeset,AHisto- ryofGreekPhilosophy,providesanoutstandinghistoricalanalysisofancient classical philosophy, but his convictions as a lay minister at his college chapel may have biased his analysis more than he realized. This tendency seems likely, for example, when he suggested the possibility of shared am- bivalence toward religious belief by both of the pre-Socratic philosophers, ParmenidesandMelissus: AgainstthosewhospeakofmysticismandproofsoftheexistenceofGod,itis necessarytopointoutthat,evenifParmenidesandMelissusretained,almost vii viii Preface automatically,thislegacyfromearlierthought,theirremainsshowthatitwas oflittleimportancetothem.2 In simpler terms, religion was presumably retained by both philosophers at least as common assumptions otherwise of little importance later in their lives. Guthrie could obscure the religious disbelief of Melissus, as indicated inapassagequotedbyDiogenesLaertiusinLivesofEminentPhilosophers: Moreover,he[Melissus]saidthatweoughtnottomakeanystatementsabout thegods,foritwasimpossibletohaveknowledgeofthem.”3 Thiswasasuccinctadmissionofagnosticism--ifnotatheism--andinfact it anticipated the viewpoint of modern logical positivists including Bertrand Russell,Guthrie’scolleagueatCambridge. In contrast, Theodor Gomperz, the eminent Austrian classicist who lived atthesame time as Burnet seemsto havesuggestedthelikelihood of Melis- sus’impietywhenheaccusedhimofaninexcusabletransgression,butwith- outgoingsofarastoidentifyit: Gravefallaciesmustbelaidtohischarge,butthereisnottheleastgroundto imputetohimanydeliberateimpostureoranydeceptionsavethedeceptionof himself.4 Grave fallacies indeed! One can only suppose that Melissus’ refusal to concede the necessary existence of gods was considered so extreme that it had to be ignored except as an unspeakable transgression. Unfortunately, however, this avoidance that Gomperz shared with Burnet and Guthrie servedtoobscurethepivotalsignificanceofMelissus’primaryassumption— the recognition that the combination of spatial and temporal infinitude, the latteras already suggestedbyParmenides, seemsto eliminate thelikelihood of transcendental godhead. Of necessity a functional god along with the promise of an afterlife could only be possible as co-extensive portions of material existence in its entirety. Melissus accordingly declared an assump- tion implicit in ancient Greek philosophy from its very beginning, and in doing so he bridged the gap from Parmenides’ holistic perspective asserted byclassicalgoddesses atleastforliteraryeffect to theoutspokenatheismof Democritus, Protagoras, and an assortment of Athenian Sophists, followed by Aristotle and still later by Strato, Carneades and even Cicero. Unfortu- nately,modernignoranceofthispredominantsecularassumptionthroughout ancient Greek philosophy obscures an important historic linkage between whatmightseemtwoseparateperiodsinthehistoryofancientGreekphilos- ophy—pre-SocraticsecularphilosophyandAristoteliancosmologythatturns outtohavebeenequallysecularoncesubmittedtocloseexamination.

Description:
An Archaeology of Disbelief traces the origin of secular philosophy to pre-Socratic Greek philosophers who proposed a physical universe without supernatural intervention. Some mentioned the Homeric gods, but others did not. Atomists and Sophists identified themselves as agnostics if not outright ath
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.