ebook img

Ambiguities in Intensional Contexts PDF

334 Pages·1981·9.709 MB·Synthese Language Library 12
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Ambiguities in Intensional Contexts

AMBIGUITIES IN INTENSIONAL CONTEXTS SYNTHESE LANGUAGE LIBRARY TEXTS AND STUDIES IN LINGUISTICS AND PHILOSOPHY Managing Editors: J A A K K 0 HI N T I K K A, Florida State University STANLEY PETERS, The University of Texas at Austin Editorial Board: EM M 0 N B A C H, University of Massachusetts at Amherst J 0 A N B RES NAN, Massachusetts Institute of Technology J 0 H N L YON S, University ofS ussex JULIUS M. E. MORAVCSIK, Stanford University PATRICK S UPPE S, Stanford University DAN A S COT T, Oxford University VOLUME 12 AMBIGUITIES IN INTENSIONAL CONTEXTS Edited by FRANK HE NY Groningen University D. REIDEL PUBLISHING COMPANY DORDRECHT: HOLLAND/BOSTON: U. S.A. LONDON: ENGLAND Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Main entry under title: Ambiguities in intensional contexts. (Synthese language library; v. 12) Bibliography: p. Includes index. 1. Semantics - Addresses, essays, lectures. 2. Ambiguity - Addresses, essays, lectures. 3. Language and logic - Addresses, essays, lectures. 4. Pragmatics - Addresses, essays, lectures. I. Heny, Frank. II. Series. P325.A425 415 80-25888 ISBN-13: 978-90-277-1168-7 e-ISBN-13: 978-94-009-8377-9 001: 10.1007/978-94-009-8377-9 Published by D. Reidel Publishing Company, P.O. Box 17, 3300 AA Dordrecht, Holland. Sold and distributed in the U.S.A. and Canada by Kluwer Boston Inc., 190 Old Derby Street, Hingham, MA 02043, U.S.A. In all other countries, sold and distributed by Kluwer Academic Publishers Group, P.O. Box 322, 3300 AH Dordrecht, Holland. D. Reidel Publishing Company is a member of the Kluwer Group. All Rights Reserved Copyright © 1981 by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any informational storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner. T ABLE OF CONTENTS PREFACE vii INTRODUCTION ix ESA SAARINEN / Quantifier Phrases Are (At Least) Five Ways Ambiguous in Intensional Contexts 1 LARS HELLAN / On Semantic Scope 47 EWAN KLEIN / Defensible Descriptions 83 DAVID WOODRUFF SMITH / The Ortcutt Connection 103 DAVID SCHWARZ / Reference and Relational Belief: On Causality and the Pragmatics of 'Referring To' and 'Believing About' 133 JEROEN GROENENDIJK and MARTIN STOKHOF / A Pragmatic Analysis of Specificity 153 BARRY RICHARDS / Pronouns, Reference and Semantic Laziness 191 EVA EJERHED / Tense as a Source of Intensional Ambiguity 231 THEO M. V. JANSSEN and PETER VAN EM DE BOAS / On Intensionality in Programming Languages 253 INDEX OF NAMES 271 INDEX OF SUBJECTS 277 PREFACE The essays in this book deal with a number of problems in the analysis of intensional language - more especially with the analysis of the personal modalities in natural language. Together they cover a representative spectrum of the problems of contemporary ,interest in this area, in a way that should make them of interest to linguists, logicians and philosophers concerned with natural language. The contributors are mostly more linguists than logicians or philosophers but some are more logicians or philosophers than linguists. As far as possible, we have tried to conduct the discussion in terms that will enable students from any of these fields to come to grips with the central issues. This volume will provide, I think, material for a very stimulating course. I have used it as the basis for a course at the introductory level in the philosophy of language. The essays in the book led us back to look at the classic texts and a good deal of the intervening literature crept in of its own accord. Out of that experience grew the introduction that follows. In contrast with the rest of the book, the introduction is frankly pedagogical. I hope and believe that many who would otherwise find the papers themselves hard to digest will ~e helped on their way by that summary. Perhaps such emphasis on the attempts to make the material accessible to students will create the impression that the papers themselves are simply pedagogical. They are not. All are original research contributions. The idea for this book originated at an informal get-together at my house, in Kiel Windeweer, Holland, one weekend in September 1977. Most of the contributors were present on that occasion; most of the papers were read, discussed or dreamed up over that weekend - at least in some embryonic form. Then the volume grew a little. Because of the way in which the volume originated and grew and changed, the publication of some of the papers has been delayed for some time. I appreciate the patience of those who have waited, and I thank them for it. I should also like to thank those who came to Kiel Windeweer and have no paper in this volume for their unseen contri butions. Thanks, also, to the members of my philosophy of language seminar for helping to shape the introduction, and to Jet van Everdingen and Hermie Zondervan-Kimsma for help with the typing. August 1980 FRANK HENY vii INTRODUCTION 1. NAMES, THINGS, LANGUAGE AND THOUGHT Most of the essays in this collection deal with problems that arise when language, though perfectly meaningful, seems to be functioning without the normal bonds between names, descriptions or quantifying expressions and those things which usually give them meaning. In general such phenomena occur in contexts that are easily recognizable by the presence of a 'logical' adverb like necessarily or possibly; a verb expressing someone's intentions, like hope, seek, want, or someone's attitude towards a state of affairs, like believe, regret, surmise; or a tense-like operator such as the future modal, will. This list is far from exhaustive. In all the examples, and many more that could be given, ambiguities arise. And language seems to lose its hold on the things of the world. There are things. And things (sometimes) have names. We can use these names to identify and hence to think and talk about the things they name. If the world were just things, and if language were nothing but names - more accurately, if the world were a fIxed set of pre-identifIed things, each supplied with a distinct and unambiguous name, and if language were just that set of names - then there would be little of interest to say about language. (And no way to say it!) But neither language nor the world is so simple. To begin with, there are linguistic expressions which, if they are names at all, name sometimes one thing, sometimes another. What they name depends on the changing properties of the things rather than upon their identity. So the sentence Ralph is talking to the owner of the supermarket may be true today if Ralph is talking today to Smith; tomorrow if he is talking to Brown. Brown on the other hand is in no wise Smith; Smith tomorrow remains himself. And to add to the confusion he remains Smith even if he changes his name to Jones ... or even Brown. He remains the same person, the same individual, even if he sells his store, changes his name, and ... well, it is really not very clear how much he can change and remain himself. But that is not a problem we can try to solve here. We are concerned with language and with its relation to things, and though this will inevitably bring us right to the brink of asking about the ix x INTRODUCTION nature of the things themselves, we must stop short of seeking an answer to that. On the other hand, there are times when language seems able to function without any direct relation to things at all, no matter how abstract. "Ralph is looking for the owner of the supermarket", I may say. "But he is under a misapprehension. It is a communal enterprise." There is no owner, and I knew it; yet I used the phrase the owner of the supermarket in a per fectly normal fashion and even succeeded in saying something by means of that usage. We need to ask how that can be. In many contexts where it seems that language can function perfectly well without naming or describing anything at all- even when a name or descrip tion is used - the linguistic expressions act in a peculiar way. Here is an example. Ralph is talking to the owner of the supermarket. The owner, we have agreed, is the president of the sports club. So Ralph is talking to the president of the sports club. But if Ralph tells the owner of the super market that he is looking for the president of the sports club - not knowing who that is: is he then also looking for the owner of the supermarket? Or take Ralph's brother: he believes that the president of the sports club is good at tennis. He need not believe that the owner of the supermarket plays at all. The beliefs, the searches (the hopes and fears, and many other attitudes) all seem to be phrasable only in terms of specific linguistic expressions. Language itself can sometimes, in those cases, provide the things which it names or describes.1 Then, since our subject is language, we do need to know more about the things themselves. For they are language. When language seems to name nothing, then it is most likely to be naming or describing linguistic objects. Does that mean that the non-existent supermarket owner of a few paragraphs back, Smith, the president of the club and so on are all, in some elusive sense, abstract linguistic objects in so far as they playa role in the meanings of these sentences? It would be neater if that were not so. It is hard to conceive of the non-existent owner of the supermarket as a linguistic object. At any rate, there sometimes seem too few things for the available names. This super-abundance of names can arise in quite another way, too. For the things that do have names tend to be blessed with a great number of names. Smith is now not only the owner of the supermarket but the president of the sports club. These are not names which like 'Smith' will change, if ever, only a sort of re-baptism,2 but depend on Smith's properties. Still, like 'Smith' they apply uniquely, and can be used to identify Smith. There are yet other expressions which apply to Smith but not uniquely. These we can barely regard as names in any sense,3 though if Smith is wearing a red tie then he is indeed correctly described by the phrase a man in a red tie. INTRODUCTION xi If I know no other way of identifying him, I may say, "A man in a red tie was looking for you". Whether I was naming, or referring to Smith is another question, and for the present we shall concentrate on uniquely identifying descriptions and proper names rather than such indeftnite, quantifying ex pressions. But quantifted expressions misbehave, like names, in these contexts, as evidenced by the ambiguity of Ralph is looking for a man in a red tie. One term that has been used for the contexts in which such problems arise is 'opaque'.4 Expressions in these contexts, behaving as if they have no reference at all in the real world have been regarded as 'referentially opaque'. Interestingly, they may, in the same contexts function is another way, so that they retain (almost) their full normal, 'transparent' referential properties.5 Let us go back to Ralph's brother. We failed to derme precisely what it was he really believed. On the one hand, he might just have heard a convincing rumor about the president's tennis game, without having any idea who the president is; on the other hand, he may know who the president is and believe of him that he plays a good game. In the ftrst case, there is no-one of whom we can say, "Ralph's brother believes he plays well." In the second case, there is. Even in the second case, we might hesitate to say that Ralph's brother believes of the owner of the supermarket that he plays well-if the identity of the owner is unknown to him. But otherwise the behavior of the terms involved seems normal. They refer, albeit not so as to be fully transparent. As a second example, take Ralph's search for the president of the sports club. In the scenario above, he was already talking to the president. So he is searching, not for someone whom he has identified as the president, but simply for whoever turns out to be the president. When the sentence is understood in this way, it would not affect the truth of the sentence in any way if there were no president of the sports club. For the other reading, we must suppose that Ralph slightly knows the president, and is searching for him personally. There is someone for whom he is looking. But in his search he is given a number, which he calls, only to ftnd that it is the number of the super market - where it is not known that the owner is the club president. Is Ralph telling the truth if he denies that he is looking for the owner of the supermarket? Arguably. Apart from the specific linguistic expressions that seem to characterize opaque contexts, and the ambiguity, there are two kinds of phenomena which are sometimes regarded as criterial. On the one hand, substitution under identity may fail to preserve truth; on the other, existential generaliz ation may fail. The ftrst is exemplifted by the fact we cannot infer from Ralph is looking for the president of the sports club and The owner of the xii INTRODUCTION supermarket is the president of the sports club to Ralph is looking for the owner of the supermarket. Had the verb been talking to, this inference would have been justified. The second phenomenon was exemplified by the fact that Ralph's brother believes that the president of the sports club plays a good game of tennis can be true without it also being true that There is someone of whom Ralph believes that he plays a good game of tennis. A simpler example: Ralph is looking for the owner of the supermarket did not require There is someone Ralph is looking for. Ralph is talking to the owner of the supermarket requires that there be someone to whom he is talking. Expressions inducing the relevant kind of ambiguity or cases of these phenomena (which tend to go together but do not always do so) have been called 'intensional,.6 Expressions which do not do so are 'extensional'. Con texts where the ambiguity and failure of substitution or generalization occur can be called 'intensional' instead of 'opaque'. In the next section we shall explore some of the characteristics of extensional and intensional expressions. 2. EXTENSIONALITY, INTENSIONALITY AND AMBIGUITY The simplest languages do not possess the complications described above. The relationship between the expressions of such a language and the things they name or describe remains constant. They are also unambiguous. We approach the description of ambiguity in intensional contexts by reflecting briefly on what it would be like for natural language to be like that. Among the unambiguous, extensional languages is first order predicate logic. The expressions of predicate logic depend for their truth value solely on the extension of the predicates which they include. The extension of a predicate is the set of entities which possess the attribute in question. For a predicate F and a domain of entities D, every individual member of D is either F or not F. The extension of F in D is that subset of D which contains all those members of D which are F. If the domain of quantification is fixed in this way, then the truth (in D) of Vx Fx, Ax Fx, AxVy Gxy, VyAx Gxy will be the values of (different) functions of the extension of the predicates F and G (in D). When there is at least one member of D that is F, the first will be true; a single entity in not-F will falsify the second; and the third and fourth, while potentially differing in value in accordance with the interpretation of the differing scopes of the universal and existential quantifiers, will ultimately depend on the extension of the predicate G. A binary predicate like G will be represented not as a subset of D, but as a set of ordered pairs of members of D. From the set of all such pairs the

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.