ebook img

Altruism in Humans PDF

321 Pages·2011·1.9 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Altruism in Humans

Altruism in Humans Oxford University Press, Inc., publishes works that further Oxford University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education. Oxford New York Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto With offices in Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam Copyright © 2011 by Oxford University Press, Inc. Published by Oxford University Press, Inc. 198 Madison Avenue, New York, New York 10016 www.oup.com Oxford is a registered trademark of Oxford University Press All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior permission of Oxford University Press. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Batson, C. Daniel (Charles Daniel), 1943-Altruism in humans / C. Daniel Batson. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-0-19-534106-5 (hbk.: alk. paper) 1. Altruism. I. Title. BF637.H4B387 2011 155.2'32—dc22 2010021456 ISBN-13: 978-0-19-534106-5 ISBN-10: 0-19-534106-6 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper iv Contents Introduction 3 Part I A Theory of Altruistic Motivation 9 1 The Empathy-Altruism Hypothesis 11 2 Antecedents of Empathic Concern 33 3 Behavioral Consequences of Empathy-Induced Altruism 59 Part II Empirical Evidence 81 4 Turning to Experiments 83 5 Testing the Empathy-Altruism Hypothesis 110 6 Two Further Challenges 135 Part III Altruism in Action 161 7 Benefits of Empathy-Induced Altruism 163 8 Liabilities 188 9 Toward a Pluralism of Prosocial Motives—and a More Humane Society 207 v Summary and Conclusion 228 References 235 Appendix A Cross-cutting Independent Variable(s), Dependent Variable(s), and Competing Predictions that Can Test the Empathy-Altruism Hypothesis Against Each Egoistic Alternative 269 Appendix B Tests of the Aversive-Arousal-Reduction Hypothesis 275 Appendix C Tests of the Social-Evaluation Version of the Empathy- Specific-Punishment Hypothesis 281 Appendix D Tests of the Self-Evaluation Version of the Empathy- Specific-Punishment Hypothesis 285 Appendix E Tests of the General Empathy-Specific-Reward Hypothesis 289 Appendix F Tests of the Empathic-Joy Version of the Empathy-Specific- Reward Hypothesis 293 Appendix G Tests of the Negative-State-Relief Version of the Empathy- Specific-Reward Hypothesis 297 Author Index 303 Subject Index 317 vi Introduction What is the role of altruism in human life? To answer this question, it is necessary first to know whether altruism—a desire to benefit someone else for his or her sake rather than one’s own—even exists in humans. The existence of altruism has been debated, often hotly, for centuries. One reason for heated debate is that if altruism exists, it has profound implications. Its existence speaks not only to how we should direct our energies but also to a fundamental question about human nature: Is everything we humans do, no matter how noble and seemingly selfless, actually directed toward benefiting ourselves? Those who carefully ponder the human condition often conclude that self-interest underlies all our actions. The wise and witty Duke de la Rochefoucauld did: “The most disinterested love is, after all, but a kind of bargain, in which the dear love of our own selves always proposes to be the gainer some way or other” (Maxim 82, 1691). Many philosophers and scientists, both before and since, have reached similar conclusions. If they are right, then it is important that we recognize this fact about human nature, lest fanciful dreams of altruism seduce us into counterproductive sentimentality and doomed efforts at social reform. But there is reason to think that they are not right. I wish to make a case that altruism does exist in humans. The case includes outlining a theory of altruistic motivation, reviewing evidence obtained from direct tests of the central tenet of the theory, reviewing evidence relevant to related issues, and considering the implications of the theory at both a conceptual and a practical level. Not only do I wish to make a case that altruism exists; I also wish to present evidence that altruism is an important force in human affairs. Indeed, the evidence suggests that altruism is far more pervasive and powerful than has been recognized. Failure to appreciate its importance has handicapped attempts to understand why we humans act as we do and wherein our happiness lies. This failure has also handicapped efforts to promote better interpersonal relations and a more caring, humane society. Many, especially within religious traditions, have said that we humans ought to be altruistic. I shall not engage this issue, at least not directly. As a scientist, my concern is with what is, not what ought to be. Philosophers would say my goal is descriptive, not normative. Of course, “ought” and “is” are not totally unrelated. We can only be expected to do what is within our capacity. 3 Where to Look for Evidence A second reason for heated debate over altruism is that clear evidence for its existence is not easily found. Advocates of altruism typically appeal to dramatic examples of heroism, rescue, and self-sacrifice to make their case. These examples highlight the possibility that we can care for others, not simply for ourselves. But even the most stirring examples of heroic helpfulness fail to provide clear and convincing evidence of altruism. As la Rochefoucauld suggested, the possibility remains that the hero or saint acted to benefit the self “some way or other.” It may seem tasteless to scrutinize the motives of a person who risked his or her life to shelter those trying to escape from the Holocaust, of firemen who died while directing others to safety after the attack on the World Trade Center, or of a person who pulls an injured child from shark-infested waters. But if we really want to know whether humans can be altruistically motivated, such scrutiny is necessary. And under scrutiny, we must admit that even heroes and saints may have done their good deeds for other than altruistic reasons: Perhaps they felt compelled to act in order to avoid having to live with the knowledge that they did nothing. Perhaps they were seeking the rewards of seeing themselves—or being seen by others—as a good person. Perhaps they sought rewards in an imagined life to come. Perhaps they were simply reacting to situational pressure without any clear goal in mind. “What else could I do?” is a common response when rescuers are asked why they risked life and limb to save a stranger. Although this response may reflect modesty, it may also be an accurate depiction of what was seen as a lack of other options at the time. The altruistic motivation for which I wish to make a case is not the exclusive province of heroes and saints. It is neither exceptional nor unnatural. Rather, I shall argue that altruism is a motivational state that virtually all of us frequently visit. Although its origins are not yet fully understood, I suspect they lie at least in part in the nurturant impulse of human parents to care for their young. This impulse has been strongly selected for within our evolutionary history. Without it, our species would have vanished long ago. Perhaps because altruism based on nurturance is so thoroughly woven into the fabric of our lives, is so commonplace and so natural, its importance has failed to be recognized. As long as we assume that altruism, if it exists at all, is rare and unnatural, we are likely to seek it on the edges of our experience in acts of extreme self-sacrifice. We are not likely to look at the everyday experience of people like you and me. I wish to argue that it is in such experience that we can find the clearest evidence of the role altruism plays in human life. Yet we cannot see this evidence through simple observation. Using Experiments Evidence of the existence and importance of altruism can be most clearly seen, I believe, by observing the responses of ordinary people in carefully contrived experiments designed to tease apart possible motives for acting to benefit another. These experiments come out 4 of a tradition of laboratory research on the nature of human motives that has developed in social psychology over the past seventy years. The artificiality and trickery of the social- psychology laboratory may seem unlikely tools to use in the search for altruism. However, once the issues are clearly laid out, I think it will become apparent that contrived and deceptive laboratory experiments offer an ideal way to unearth evidence, pro and con, regarding altruism. Such experiments have the potential to provide much clearer evidence than is provided either by (a) natural observation—whether observation of humans, even heroic humans, or of other species—or by (b) theoretical deduction— even deduction from such powerful theories as the theory of natural selection or the theory of rational choice. Armchair speculation about the motives behind heroic acts or about theoretical possibilities is both fun and popular. Over the past several decades, it has produced a number of books and articles about altruism in humans. This speculation has not provided satisfactory answers to our questions about the existence of altruism and about the role altruism plays in human life. It has not because it cannot. Questions about the existence and role of altruism are not questions about possibility; they are about reality. They are not questions about what might be or what ought to be; they are about what is. A careful, controlled look at what is—at when and, more importantly, at why people act to benefit someone else—is the only way to provide satisfactory answers. Addressing these questions by use of experiments is not the easiest way; it is not the most popular way. But if we want to find answers that go beyond speculation and possibility, I think use of experiments is the best way. Before seeking answers, however, we must understand more clearly what we are looking for. To this end, Part I of this book offers a theory of altruistic motivation. Then Part II provides a summary of the empirical evidence for the existence of altruism. Finally, Part III considers the role of altruism in human life. Audience When colleagues—or publishers—hear that you are writing a book, one of the first questions is about audience. Given that this book is about altruism, I am embarrassed to admit that I wrote it primarily for myself. Having read about, thought about, and researched altruism for over thirty years, I wanted to record where my thinking and the empirical evidence has led me, and to do so before drifting off into my dotage. My goal was to provide as complete and accurate a record as possible. Of course, a detailed record has the painful virtue of exposing gaps. I tried to resist hiding or glossing over these, leaving them bare and exposed for future work. In spite of writing mainly for myeslf, I very much hope others will be interested in reading over my shoulder. To this end, I have tried to make the book accessible to a range of readers—not only colleagues, graduate students, and advanced undergraduates in social psychology but also those interested in altruism from other academic disciplines, including philosophy, biology, economics, sociology, anthropology, and theology, as well 5 as from applied fields such as business, law, nursing, medicine, and ministry. Of course, one need not fit a disciplinary niche to have an interest in the role of altruism in human life. So I have written with the nonprofessional reader in mind too. Altruism is not an easy topic; there are many conceptual subtleties, inferential complexities, and empirical challenges that cannot be usefully addressed by oversimplification. But neither can they be usefully addressed by obfuscation. Throughout, I have tried to be as clear and direct as possible, while not shying away from complexity. One implication of writing for myself is that I have cited a lot of other people’s work to remind me—and to inform readers—of sources I have found useful along the way. For the most part, these citations are done parenthetically so as not to slow down the through- reader who wishes to forego side trails. I have also tried to highlight points of difference and disagreement where such points exist, and to state as clearly as possible why I favor the position I do. As will be apparent, I have benefited greatly from the ideas and research of those with whom I disagree. In turn, I hope they also may find some of my ideas and research useful. For readers familiar with my earlier book, The Altruism Question (1991), let me say how this book relates to it. First, even though the two books share a focus on the empathy- altruism hypothesis—the claim that empathic concern produces altruistic motivation— there are important conceptual differences. The empathy-altruism hypothesis is explicated in far more detail here, providing the basis for a more comprehensive theory of human altruism (Chapters 1–3) that includes a revised formulation of the antecedents of empathic concern (Chapter 2). Second, although the research designed to test the empathy-altruism hypothesis available at the time of the earlier book is reviewed here as well, so is much new research. Because the body of research testing this hypothesis is now quite large, it is presented in summary form in Chapter 5 and in appendices to provide easy access and assessment. Third, several important challenges to the empathy-altruism hypothesis have come to the fore since the earlier book, and research relevant to these challenges is reviewed here for the first time (Chapter 6). Fourth, in recent years, research has moved beyond the question of the existence of empathy-induced altruism to consider theoretical and practical implications of its existence. That research is reviewed in Chapters 7–9. Finally, the earlier book was rather narrowly focused on research in experimental social psychology designed to test the empathy-altruism hypothesis. Although that research is central here as well, the broader theoretical perspective of this book includes attention to recent work in philosophy, neuroscience, evolutionary biology, primatology, behavioral economics, sociology, and anthropology. Appreciation Over the almost fifteen years I have worked on this book, many colleagues, students, and friends provided valuable input, for which I am profoundly grateful. Naming them here does not do justice to their various contributions. (Nor does naming them mean that they agree with my conclusions.) And doubtless, I have failed to think of everyone who 6 should be listed, for which I apologize. With those provisos, sincere thanks to: Nadia Ahmad, Monica Biernat, James Blair, Jack Brehm, Sarah Brosnan, Stephanie Brown, Sue Carter, Bob Cialdini, Nancy Collins, Mark Davis, Karen Dawson, Jean Decety, Frans de Waal, Nancy Eisenberg, Jakob Eklund, Nick Epley, Ernst Fehr, Jim Fultz, Lowell Gaertner, Adam Galinsky, Omri Gillath, Maria Guibert, Eddie Harmon-Jones, Grit Hein, Tom Insel, Claus Lamm, Mel Lerner, David Lishner, Sam McFarland, Heidi Maibom, Josh May, Mario Mikulincer, Jason Mitchell, Luis Oceja, Lou Penner, Alicia Pérez- Albéniz, Jane Piliavin, Stephen Post, Daniel Povinelli, Stephanie Preston, Adam Powell, Pete Richerson, Dave Schroeder, Phil Shaver, Laura Shaw, Joan Silk, Tania Singer, Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, Elliott Sober, Steve Stich, Eric Stocks, Karsten Stueber, Michael Tomasello, Jo-Ann Tsang, Felix Warneken, and Carolyn Zahn-Waxler. Special thanks to Jack Dovidio, Martha Nussbaum, and Matthieu Ricard, each of whom provided insightful and extremely helpful comments on the manuscript as a whole. Special thanks also to Lori Handelman and Abby Gross of Oxford University Press for their enthusiasm, encouragement, and support throughout the publication process. For about ten years, my research on altruism benefited greatly from National Science Foundation support. Speaking of support, this book probably would not be without Ben. Finally, special thanks to my wife Judy for her involvement from start to finish—her readiness to talk altruism over drinks again and again, her exceptional insight as a pilot research participant, her care and dedication assisting with data collection, her comments on chapter drafts, her editorial skill, and her overall patience, understanding, and support. Who could ask for more? 7

Description:
Batson, C. Daniel (Charles Daniel), 1943-Altruism in humans / C. Daniel Batson. p. cm. Second, although my definition of empathic emotion is . the PAM with a Russian doll metaphor, claiming that, as in a set of Russian dolls, mimicry or imitation is an active, goal-directed process even in infants
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.