ebook img

Aeneas of Gaza : Theophrastus with Zacharias of Mytilene, Ammonius PDF

216 Pages·2012·2.171 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Aeneas of Gaza : Theophrastus with Zacharias of Mytilene, Ammonius

AENEAS OF GAZA Theophrastus with ZACHARIAS OF MYTILENE Ammonius This page intentionally left blank AENEAS OF GAZA Theophrastus Translated by John Dillon and Donald Russell with ZACHARIAS OF MYTILENE Ammonius Translated by Sebastian Gertz LONDON • NEW DELHI • NEW YORK • SYDNEY Bloomsbury Academic An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc 50 Bedford Square 1385 Broadway London New York WC1B 3DP NY 10018 UK USA www.bloomsbury.com Bloomsbury is a registered trade mark of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc First published in 2012 by Bristol Classical Press Paperback edition (cid:2) rst published 2014 Preface © 2012 by Richard Sorabji Translation © 2012 by Sebastian Gertz, John Dillon, and Donald Russell Richard Sorabji, Sebastian Gertz, John Dillon, and Donald Russell have asserted their right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identi(cid:2) ed as Authors of this work. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers. No responsibility for loss caused to any individual or organization acting on or refraining from action as a result of the material in this publication can be accepted by Bloomsbury Academic or the author. British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. ISBN HB: 978-1-7809-3209-5 PB: 978-1-4725-5801-5 ePDF: 978-1-4725-0037-3 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data A catalog record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. The present translations have been made possible by generous and imaginative funding from the following sources: the National Endowment for the Humanities, Division of Research Programs, an independent federal agency of the USA; the Leverhulme Trust; the British Academy; the Jowett Copyright Trustees; the Royal Society (UK); Centro Internazionale A. Beltrame di Storia dello Spazio e del Tempo (Padua); Mario Mignucci; Liverpool University; the Leventis Foundation; the Arts and Humanities Research Council; Gresham College; the Esmée Fairbairn Charitable Trust; the Henry Brown Trust; Mr and Mrs N. Egon; the Netherlands Organisation for Scienti(cid:2) c Research (NWO/GW); the Ashdown Trust; Dr Victoria Solomonides, the Cultural Attaché of the Greek Embassy in London; Robert Bagnall; and the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council in Canada. The editor wishes to thank Deborah Blake, the publisher responsible for every volume since the (cid:2) rst. Detailed acknowledgements are provided in ‘Note on the composition of the present volume’. Typeset by Ray Davies Printed and bound in Great Britain Contents Preface by Richard Sorabji vii Note on the Composition of the Present Volume xxxi Conventions xxxii Note on Citations xxxiii Aeneas of Gaza: Theophrastus 1 Introduction 3 Translation 11 Variations from Colonna’s Text 54 Notes 55 English-Greek Glossary 69 Greek-English Index 81 Zacharias of Mytilene: Ammonius 93 Introduction 95 Translation 101 Variations from Colonna’s Text 148 Notes 149 English-Greek Glossary 159 Greek-English Index 168 Subject Index 177 Aeneas of Gaza: Theophrastus 177 Zacharias of Mytilene: Ammonius 179 This page intentionally left blank Preface: Waiting for Philoponus Richard Sorabji I. Three Gazan Christians waiting for Philoponus The fifth-century AD pagan Neoplatonist Proclus wrote eighteen arguments for the eternity of the cosmos which were to be recorded and attacked one by one in the following century by the Christian Philoponus in his Against Proclus On the Eternity of the World.1 By ‘the world’ (kosmos in Greek) was meant the entire universe envis- aged as an orderly system, and they agreed with each other that the universe was an orderly system, even when they used an expression, ‘the universe’ (to pan in Greek), that did not actually include that in its meaning. Their disagreement was on whether it had a beginning and end, as the Christians said. Proclus died in 485 AD, and Philo- ponus wrote his reply, the first of a series against the pagan philoso- phers, in 529. In the period of almost fifty years between 485 and 529, three Christians from Gaza had already attempted to attack the dominant pagan philosophy of Platonism. They had some limited successes, but I shall argue that it was only Philoponus who had the ability to carry the attack home into the pagan camp.2 Three Christian attacks on Neoplatonism Aeneas of Gaza was the first of the three Gazans. His dialogue Theophrastus, written between 485 and 490,3 was named after his fictitious Platonist interlocutor who represented the case for Plato- nism and who supposedly lost to the fictitious Christian Euxitheus. The main subject of the Theophrastus was the human soul and its fate before birth and after death, including the resurrection. But it overlapped in one part with the subject of the other two Christian texts, the Christians’ creation of the world from a beginning, as opposed to the Neoplatonists’ eternal creation of the world. Moreover, the overlap turns out to be greater, because the second Christian also finishes his text by discussing the resurrection. The second Christian, Zacharias, born in the port of Gaza, Mai- uma, had gone to study rhetoric and philosophy in Alexandria in the 480s. After moving on to study law in Berytus around 487, he wrote viii Waiting for Philoponus in the 490s a dialogue caricaturing the great Neoplatonist philo- sopher of Alexandria, Ammonius, and named it after him, Ammonius (or On the Creation of the World). This dialogue represented Am- monius as being refuted and silenced by the arguments about creation of a Christian student identified in the preface as Zacharias himself, even though he warns that when he is in dialogue with the two pagan professors, he will switch his designation from ‘A’ to ‘CH.’ (short for ‘Christian’), as he does several times.4 It cited Aeneas a couple of times, and re-used some of his arguments, although it added many more, often naïve, but occasionally better than those of Aeneas. Zacharias was to feature as the hero in another of his own treatises, The Life of Severus, this time as the most important figure in a riot of about 486 that ransacked the pagan temple of Isis outside Alexandria, and led to the flight from the city of three pagan teach- ers, the torture of another, and the death in hiding of a fifth. The Ammonius inserted the supposed refutation by Zacharias of Gessius, a younger medical colleague of Ammonius, and it has been suggested that this ‘refutation’ was added after 525 AD, when Ammonius was no longer alive himself to provide the straw man.5 The dialogue is amusingly unreal in its boasts, but also sociologically interesting, as it reveals much about the practices in the Alexandrian school, which has recently been excavated,6 and about the feelings of a zealous and dangerously disruptive sub-group of Christian students. Zacharias finished up as the Bishop of Mytilene. As regards a third Christian, Procopius of Gaza (died c. 538), it has been drawn to my attention7 that there are two pages in Procopius’ Commentary on Genesis8 that argue against the eternity of the world, and this battery of summarised arguments includes a few that are more skilful than those that we find in Zacharias. Procopius himself had a brother called Zacharias, but it is not known whether that Zacharias was ours. The anti-Platonist arguments of the last two Gazans very occa- sionally anticipate those found in Philoponus. But we shall see that they cannot be compared. One important factor is that Philoponus does repeatedly what the Gazans do only occasionally. He takes on his Platonist opponents on their own terms, using their premises to arrive at his conclusion. Not even Proclus had done that in writing against the Christians, and Philoponus often complains in his Against Proclus that Proclus is relying on Platonist dogma which he, Philoponus, finds unpersuasive and sometimes absurd. This is only one of the reasons why I have described the Christian opponents of Neoplatonism as ‘waiting for Philoponus’. But the situ- ation has been illuminatingly nuanced by Edward Watts. It is not that the three Gazans were trying to do the same thing as Philoponus and failing. On the contrary, Watts has argued, in discussing the first two of the three Gazans, that they had more parochial aims.9 On this Waiting for Philoponus ix account, it turns out to be only natural that they did not feel it necessary to refute the Platonists on their own terms. Aeneas was a rhetorician, and Watts argues that the readers he wanted to impress were in the literary salons especially of Alexandria and regarded themselves as being on equal, and not unfriendly, terms with the Neoplatonists. Zacharias, by contrast, was writing to impress certain Christian students in Alexandria and to undercut the personal authority of their pagan teachers in religious matters. Neither ques- tioned the value of Neoplatonist cultural knowledge, and Aeneas was interested in displaying his rhetorical acquaintance with it. Both might presumably have achieved their objectives, without showing the Neoplatonists themselves that their philosophical position was untenable, which is what Philoponus set out to do. Watts offers a hypothesis about Philoponus’ motivation, which must inevitably remain conjectural.10 But it would, if true, explain the fact that Philoponus opposed the Neoplatonists on their own terms. Up to about 525 AD Philoponus had edited by far the largest number of commentaries on Aristotle based on Ammonius’ lectures, with innovative contributions of his own.11 From 529 onwards, while writing at least one more commentary on Aristotle, he embarked on a series of attacks on the pagan world-view of Aristotle and Proclus. Watts’ suggestion is that, on finding he was passed over for the chair of philosophy upon the death of Ammonius’ immediate successor around 525 in favour of the very much less experienced Olympio- dorus, he decided that he could attract Christian students away from Olympiodorus to his own better exposition of pagan thought, accom- panied by a critique of it. I shall now look more closely at the successes and limitations of the three earlier efforts to combat pagan Neoplatonism. Aeneas on the food chain objection to resurrection I shall start with an example from Aeneas’ defence of Christian views on the soul and the resurrection of the body. This makes the overlap with Zacharias complete, because Zacharias tacks on this same problem about the resurrection to his treatise on the creation of the world. Like Philoponus, Aeneas is aware of an objection to the resurrection of the body, that our bodies will be eaten after death and will have passed through a food chain, but he is unaware of the sharpest formulation of the problem given by Origen (died 253/4 AD), which motivates the solution offered by Origen and was apparently followed by Philoponus.12 The crucial point in the sharpest formula- tion is that the food chain includes other individual humans. The food chain problem was known at least as early as Athenagoras in the second century AD. Christians wanted us to be given back the very same bodies at the resurrection and the usual

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.