ebook img

Action and Responsibility PDF

200 Pages·2006·0.872 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Action and Responsibility

ACTION AND RESPONSIBILITY LIBRARYOF ETHICS AND APPLIED PHILOSOPHY VOLUME18 Managing Editor: Govert A. den Hartogh, University of Amsterdam, The Netherlands The titles published in this series are listed at the end of this volume. ACTION AND RESPONSIBILITY by ANDREW SNEDDON University of Ottawa, ON, Canada AC.I.P. Catalogue record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN-10 1-4020-3996-4 (HB) ISBN-13 978-1-4020-3996-6 (HB) ISBN-10 1-4020-3982-4 (e-book) ISBN-13 978-1-4020-3982-9 (e-book) Published by Springer, P.O. Box 17, 3300 AADordrecht, The Netherlands. www.springeronline.com Printed on acid-free paper All Rights Reserved © 2006 Springer No part of this work may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording or otherwise, without written permission from the Publisher, with the exception of any material supplied specifically for the purpose of being entered and executed on a computer system, for exclusive use by the purchaser of the work. Printed in the Netherlands. CONTENTS Acknowledgements vii Preface ix Chapter 1: Two Questions 1 Appendix I: The Status Question: What to Look For? 13 Chapter 2: Ascriptivism Resurrected: The Case for Ascriptivism 19 Chapter 3: Ascriptivism Defended: The Case Against Ascriptivism 33 Appendix II: An Alternative Reading of Hart 49 Chapter 4: Responsibility and Causation I: Legal Responsibility 51 Chapter 5: Responsibility and Causation II: Moral Responsibility 67 Chapter 6: Foundationalism and the Production Question 97 Chapter 7: Foundationalism and the Status Question: Strong Productionism 119 Appendix III: Reflections on the Pursuit of a Causal Analysis of Action 131 Chapter 8: Nouveau Volitionism 137 Chapter 9: Weak Productionism 151 Chapter 10: Concluding Reflections on Ascriptivism and Action 169 BIBLIOGRAPHY 181 INDEX 187 v ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I gratefully acknowledge permission granted to reprint the following either partially or in their entirety: 1] “Considering Causalisms”, Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review, Vol. XL (2001), no. 2, pp. 343-66. Published by the Canadian Philosophical Association and Wilfrid Laurier Press. 2] “Does Philosophy of Action Rest on a Mistake?” First published in Metaphilosophy, Vol. 32: 5 (Oct, 2001), pp. 502-522. © Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishers Ltd 2001. 3] “Prichard, Strawson, and Two Objections to Moral Sensibility Theories”, Journal of Philosophical Research, Vol. 29 (2004), pp. 289-314. Published by the Philosophy Documentation Center. 4] “Moral Responsibility: The Difference of Strawson and the Difference It Should Make,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, forthcoming as of time of publication. Published by Springer. vii PREFACE This book is an exploration of what it takes for an event to count as an action. I first became interested in this topic nearly a decade ago while working on a different topic. I kept coming across philosophers making claims about the nature of action that seemed false or at least dubious to me. As a consequence I turned to the philosophy of action directly, to get to the heart of the matter. I have wrestled with this territory ever since. I hope that, with this book, I have finally earned the intuitions that put me at odds with the philosophers I was originally reading. This book develops ideas in Part Two of my doctoral dissertation, which I wrote at Queen’s University in Kingston, Ontario, Canada. I loved being at Queen’s, for both professional and personal reasons. My thanks go to the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada for financial support as a doctoral candidate. Steve Leighton and Ronald de Sousa were readers for my dissertation. They provided some early and invaluable challenges to the ideas developed here. My deepest debt of gratitude is owed to David Bakhurst, my supervisor. I learned a lot from David; this book would not be the same without his help. The earliest version of this manuscript was written during 2001-2 at the University of Calgary, where I was the Killam Postdoctoral Fellow. My thanks go to the Killam Foundation for generous support. Bob Ware was my postdoctoral supervisor at Calgary. He read and discussed the first draft. His input was very helpful, but even more important has been his friendly support, dating back to before he even met me, when I was a doctoral student soliciting help in taking the next step. It pleases me immensely to acknowledge publicly the help Bob has given me in the book that I wrote in a position that I held in large part due to his generosity. Stephen Hawkins provided invaluable assistance in preparing the manuscript for publication. My wife Debbie has been with me through every part of the process, since before the germination of the first ideas in Kingston until the writing of these words in Ottawa. I see the hands of David and Bob in particular parts of the book, but I see Debbie everywhere. This is for her. ix CHAPTER 1 TWO QUESTIONS . . . what is left over if I subtract the fact that my arm goes up from the fact that I raise my arm? Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, §621 1.QUESTIONS As has long been recognized, Wittgenstein’s question about arms rising and the raising of arms is a worthy place to begin a study of action. The reason for this is that it poses a pregnant challenge. It is a challenge because it seems like a question we, both as philosophers and as ordinary people, should be able to answer. It is pregnant, however, because it is ambiguous. On one reading, Wittgenstein’s question could be interpreted as a challenge to specify what makes an event count as an action.1 Arms rise without necessarily counting as actions. Some such movements are actions and some are not. The movement of the arm seems to be identical across such cases, so some other factor(s) must make the difference between these kinds of events. Specifying this other factor will provide an answer to the question, what makes an event count as an action? Since this question concerns the status of events qua actions, and how they come to have this status, I will call this the status question. Status Question: What makes an event count as an action? Corresponding issues will be called status issues. Terminology germane to this question and to these issues is status terminology. Looked at in another light, Wittgenstein’s question could be seen as a causal query. The action of raising one’s arm is brought about through a series of causally related events, including muscle contractions, neural activity, and the overt bodily activity mentioned in the question. The movement of the arm is at the end of this chain that somehow realizes the action. Since it is at the end, the overt bodily movement is the wrong place to look if one wants to determine how actions are produced. Subtracting the movement of arm clears the way for proper examination of the sequence of events that brought about the action. 1 Throughout, I will restrict attention to human action. For ease, I will refer just to ‘action’. 1 2 CHAPTER1 Since this version of the question emphasizes how an action is produced, I will call it the production question: Production Question: How are actions produced? As with the status question, corresponding issues are production issues, and the terminology appropriate to this sort of inquiry is production terminology. These questions will be familiar to anyone versed in contemporary philosophical study of action. Status issues are generally addressed in the attempt to develop a theory of action. Production issues come up most importantly during the development of a theory of action explanation. Alfred Mele begins a recent introduction to the field by stating that the philosophy of action is structured around two questions: ‘. . . (1) What are actions? (2) How are actions to be explained?’2 The first question is the status question. The second question, about explanation, appears different from the production question, but in fact there is much in common between the two. Twentieth century philosophy of action, from the 50s through 70s, was preoccupied wondering whether reasons could be causes. Very briefly, the issue was this: actions seem to be events explainable in terms of reasons. Reasons rationalize actions, make them intelligible. Explicating reasons that lead to actions shows the light in which the action appears favorable to the agent who performs them. All of this caused some to wonder whether they were the right sort of phenomenon to cause anything. Donald Davidson’s landmark ‘Actions, Reasons, and Causes’3 turned this debate in favour of those who thought reasons could be causes, and such a view has characterized the dominant strain of philosophy of action ever since. Seen this way, Mele’s explanation question looks very much like my production question. If reasons are causes, then a rationalizing explanation gives us some detail about the causal chain by which a given action was produced. Hence it is fair to claim that both status and production issues are at the heart of contemporary philosophy of action. A notable wrinkle appears at this point. Contemporary philosophy of action conflates the two sorts of issues. Answers to the production question are given using status terms, and vice versa; in more traditional terms, theories of action and of action explanation are deeply intertwined. Mele introduces what he calls causalism in exactly this way: A popular approach to understanding both the nature of action and the explanation of actions emphasizes causation. Causal theories of action hold that an event’s being an action depends on how it was caused. These theories feature as causes such psychological or mental items as beliefs, desires, intentions, and related events (e.g. acquiring an intention to A now). If causal theories of action are on the right track, they provide a metaphysical underpinning for a popular view of the explanation of actions— the view that actions are to be explained, causally, partly in terms of items of the kind just mentioned. The conjunction of these two ideas—one about what actions are and the other about how actions are to be explained—may be termed causalism.4 2 Alfred Mele, The Philosophy of Action, ed. Alfred Mele (Oxford, 1997), p. 1. 3 Donald Davidson, ‘Actions, Reasons, and Causes’, in Essays on Actions and Events (Oxford, 1980). 4 Mele, The Philosophy of Action, pp. 2-3.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.