ebook img

A Symposium on Kant PDF

161 Pages·1964·9.88 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview A Symposium on Kant

Tulane Studies in Philosophy Volume III A SYMPOSIUM ON KANT This volume may be purchased for $2.00, plus postage, from The Tulane University Bookstore, New Orleans 18, La. TABLE OF CONTENTS F 0 RE w 0 RD---------------·-------------------------------------------------------------------------- 5 THE K.ANTIAN SoLUTION To THE PROBLEM oF MAN WITHIN NATURE: Edward G. Ballard______________________________________________ 7 Two LoGICS OF MoDALITY: Richard L. Barber____________________ 41 KANT AND METAPHYSics: James K. Feibleman____________________ 55 KANT, CASSIRER AND THE CONCEPT OF SPACE: Car1 H. Hamburg_ _____________________________ .________________ 89 THE RIGIDITY OF KANT's CATEGORIEs: Harold N. Lee __________ 113 NoTES ON THE JuDGMENT OF TASTE: Louise Nisbet Roberts 123 THE METAPHYSICS OF THE SEVEN FORMULATIONS OF THE MoRAL ARGUMENT: Robert Whittemore_ ___________ 133 ISBN 978-90-247-0277-0 ISBN 978-94-011-7493-0 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-011-7493-0 FOREWORD T HE past does not change; it cannot, for what has happened cannot be undone. Yet how are we to understand what has happened? Our perspective on it lies in the present, and is subject to continual change. These changes, made in the light of our new knowledge and new experience, call for fresh evaluations and constant reconsideration. It is now one hundred fifty years since the death of Immanuel Kant, and this, the third volume of Tulane Studies in Philosophy is dedicated to the commemoration of the event. The diversity of the contributions to the volume serve as one indication of Kant's persistent importance in philoso phy. His work marks one of the most enormous turns in the whole history of human thought, and there is still much to be done in estimating its achievement. His writings have not been easy to assimilate. The exposition is difficult and labored; it is replete with ambiguities, and even with what often appear to be contradictions. Such writings allow for great latitude in interpretation. Yet who would dare ·to omit Kant from the account? The force of a man's work is measured by his influence on other thinkers; and here, Kant has few superiors. Of no man whose impact upon the history of ideas has been as great as that of Kant can it be said with finality: this 5 6 TULANE STUDIES IN PHILOSOPHY is his philosophy. It is exactly because he was struggling toward ideas that outstripped the language and the concepts of his day that his writings are difficult and must be in terpreted. He was developing concepts that could not be adequately conveyed in the words of his contemporaries. We read his own words in the light of the ideas which emerge from his thought, and which have been made definite, classi fied and tagged by his successors. We have no recourse but to interpret his philosophy in the light of what grew out of it, and diverse indeed are the lines of this development. It is a measure of Kant's genius that so many different streams can equally flow from his writings. The following essays will help to take this measure by illustrating the range and diversity of the ways in which his philosophy may be understood. Probably each generation will have its own Kant; it may be hoped that the essays in the present volume will help to reveal ours. J.K.F. H.N.L. New Orleans, May, 1954. THE KANTIAN SOLUTION TO THE PROBLEM OF MAN WITHIN NATURE Edward G. Ballard K ANT is not infrequently regarded as a philosopher whose only serious concern was the rescue of Newtonian mechanics from the Humian skepticism. He certainly in tended to perform this rescue, - as a means, however, to a further end. This further end is the elaboration and defense of a doctrine which regards human nature as something other than a mere cog within the Newtonian world machine. Evidently, then, the second Critique is not an afterthought but is the designed consequent of the first. The real move ment of Kant's thought cannot be grasped, I think, unless the problems of nature and knowledge of nature be under stood as a prelude-albeit a necessary prelude-to the problem of human nature. The intent of this paper is to offer a critical presentation of these two problems with what I believe to be the Kantian emphasis. The goal of philosophy is to find a single coherent explanation of all of experience, or perhaps of the whole of reality. The way to this goal lies through a tangle of problems. It could be seen very early in the history of philosophy that this group of problems is not a simple series. For example, it will be recalled, a tension began to appear 7 8 TULANE STUDIES IN PHILOSOPHY even before Socrates' life time between speculations on nature and speculations on human nature. A solution to one of these problems appeared to render impossible a satis factory solution to the other. Thus, Democritus' atomistic and mechanistic solution to the problem of nature seemed to other philosophers either to deform man or to exclude him from the natural world. To prevent this intolerable consequence, Plato and the classic tradition built up a philosophy in which man is not reducible to nori-human elements and in which, on the contrary, nature itself is explained by analogy to · the artist. The avoidance of a mechanocentric doctrine of man seems to have entailed, for better or for worse, an anthropocentric doctrine of nature. However rich in humanistic values this classic tradition undoubtedly became, it remained poverty stricken in respect to knowledge of nature. Then, after the Renaissance dis coveries and its invention of a new method, the tables were turned and a new metaphysics, built upon the machine analogy, took the place of the classical humanistic philoso phy. Although this mechanistic doctrine was immensely fruitful in respect to physics, it did not prove to be one whit more successful than ancient atomism in providing a rationale for human nature and its values. Many thinkers came to regard mechanism as a threat to the whole culture and its human uses. The mere threat of this consequence was ground enough for a renewed anxiety which expressed itself in various formulas for modifying the naturalistic or the humanistic doctrines and. for conserving the mutually consistent features of both. But these efforts were never more than partially satisfactory. And indeed it could be suspected that the body of knowledge built upon the mechanistic analogy was radically contradictory to that reared upon the basis of the artist analogy. This opposition is recorded in various antitheses, not the least important of which is the antithesis of freedom and determinism. Kant's most characteristic trait, his unabating effort to discover unity in experience, would not permit his remain ing satisfied either with this antithesis or with any make shift adjustment between its two alternatives. His manifest desire is thoroughly to understand how human values are THE KANTIAN SOLUTION TO THE PROBLEM OF MAN 9 possible and attainable in a world of rigorously ordered physical fact. This is to hold that the doctrines in philoso phy derived from both the mechanistic analogy and the artistic analogy are coherent and possible within the same intellectural framework. If he can demonstrate the co herence of scientific knowledge with humanistic insight, then perhaps he can show in particular that human free dom is independent of the mechanical world but not contra dictory to it, and then, finally, that the human being can effect changes in the mechanical world for which he alone is responsible. In order to secure any hope of maintaining these very difficult propositions, it is evident that he will certainly be obliged to explain knowledge of nature in such a way as to exclude neither the anthropological nor the mechanical analogy, in order to uncover at least the germs of axioms which will be needed to explain the nature of value and the human pursuit of ends within a determined world. We must, therefore, move to Kant's treatment of this problem through his theory of knowledge and his theory of the nature of the physical world. The latter, issuing in the doctrine of the phenomenological object, appears at first glance to promise most favorably for the humanistic studies. The second glance, however, may be less encouraging. Pos sibly Kant merely translates the old conflict between the nature-centered and the man-centered studies into another language. Or possibly he caught at least a glimpse of their essential unity. The present discussion of these matters will be centered around the views which Kant expressed in the Critique of Pure Reason and the Prologemena. This limitation will be no handicap, for the critique of the cognitive use of reason must, in defining its own boundaries, develop the notion of the self and nature1 as well as the notion of non-human nature . . . It should be added that my ·interpretation of Kant's solution to the problem of nature must be more lengthy than the treatment of his solution to the problem of human nature, for it will be necessary to move through a criticism of a certain view (the "impositional view") of Kant's 1. Prot. S 60.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.