A Subjective and Probabilistic Approach to Derivatives U. Kirchner 0 ICAP 1 0 PO Box 1210, Houghton, 2041, South Africa 2 [email protected] n a January 11, 2010 J 1 1 Abstract tic approach with dynamic hedging. On the other ] hand one can simply calculate the expected pay-off R We propose a probabilistic framework for pricing for the log-normal probability distribution with an P derivatives,whichacknowledgesthatinformationand expected return equal to the risk-free rate. . n beliefs are subjective. Market prices can be trans- The second approach is considerably simpler, fi latedintoimpliedprobabilities. Inparticular,futures neater, anda directconsequenceof probabilisticrea- - imply returns for these implied probability distribu- soning. However,itcannotexplainwhytheexpected q [ tions. We arguethat volatilityis notrisk,butuncer- return should be equal to the risk-free rate — and tainty. Non-normal distributions combine the risk in presumably that is the reason why this derivation is 1 thelefttailwiththeopportunitiesintherighttail— hardly ever presented. v 6 unifying the “risk premium” with the possible loss. We want to offer an alternative framework in- 1 Riskandrewardmustbepartofthesamepictureand spiredbythe secondapproach,which, inessence,ac- 6 expected returns must include possible losses due to cepts the subjectivity of information/beliefs with a 1 risks. Bayesian interpretation of probabilities [1] and rein- 1. We reinterpret the Black-Scholes pricing formulas terprets the meaning of asset prices, futures, and 0 as prices for maximum-entropy probability distribu- risk. It yields the Black-Scholes pricing equations 0 tions, illuminating their importance from a new an- (but without the usual assumptions like no trading 1 gle. costs) as maximum-entropy solutions for known first : v Using these ideas we show how derivatives can be two moments, but the concept extends beyond this Xi priced under “uncertain uncertainty” and how this special case. We remove hedging arguments and re- creates a skew for the implied volatilities. place them with probabilistic reasoning1. r a We argue that the current standard approach One could best describe our approach as a proba- based on stochastic modelling and risk-neutral pric- bilistic one embracing subjectivity and Bayesian in- ing fails to account for subjectivity in markets and ference, while the traditional approach is based on mistreats uncertainty as risk. Furthermore, it is statistical/stochastic ideas and methods. These su- founded on a questionable argument — that uncer- perficially appear as if they are objective in nature tainty is eliminated at all cost. as they do not use prior distributions and do not ex- plicitly involve subjective information. This, how- 1 Introduction ever,hidesthefactthatparticularpriors(usuallyas- sumptionsaboutnormality)arealreadyassumedand TherearetwowaystojustifytheBlack-Scholesequa- 1Given the solution hedging prescriptions can then be re- tion. On the one hand there is the standardstochas- constructed. 1 hence limit the applicability of many methods. Also, risk. Consider for example the standard log-normal one could argue that the neglect of available infor- case with mationbesides historicdatais ratherashort-coming dS =µSdt+σSdX, (1) than an advantage. A good overview of these issues where X is a “normally distributed random vari- is given in [1]. able”4. It is clear that dS becomes ‘increasingly de- Thispaperisorganizedasfollows. Westartbyex- terministic’ as σ goes to zero — for σ = 0 it just posing short-comings of the traditional approach in expresses the deterministic drift. Hence we want to section 2. In section 3 we present our approach and argue that dS is really a mixture of a certain and discuss the interpretation of futures and risk. In sec- uncertain component. As one cannot eliminate the tion 4 we discuss the interpretation of Black-Scholes dependence of the portfolio value change on the dif- pricing in our context. In section 5 we present ap- ferentcomponents ofdS separately,itis notpossible plications of the probabilistic framework to pricing to follow a hedging strategy which keeps the drift, underanuncertainsecondmoment(uncertainuncer- but eliminates the randomness. tainty),whichnaturallyleadstoanimpliedvolatility Now, by eliminating dS one also discards the non- skew, derivative exposure and risk management. random drift term and the resulting hedging is gen- erally (except for a drift equal to the risk free rate) 2 The Traditional Approach suboptimal. This is most easily illustrated in ex- treme (hypothetical) cases with huge (compared to and its Problems the volatility) positive or negative drift. It appears as if it is often not understood what it The standard approach to derivatives pricing based really means to have a drift in the distribution. This on stochastic models and risk-neutral measures (see is notjustsomethingobservedinhistoricaldata,but appendix A for a short review) raises a number of somethingweclaimtoknowaboutthepossibilitiesin issues. Firstly, it does not allow for subjectivity as thefuture. Ifweusealog-normaldistributionwitha it assumes the existence of an objective “real distri- 1000% drift rate and 10% volatility then we also say bution”, and hence does not take into account that that it is practically impossible to observe a draw- peoplehavedifferentinformationandbelieves2. This down overthe next year (and even to see a return of effectively leads to the idea that there is a “correct” less than 900%) — and we claim to know this. value for a derivative, independently of its current Yetrisk-neutralpricingtellsustoignoretheknowl- trading price — it would possibly be “mispriced”. edge of the extreme drift and to hedge as if there is We think that this is misleading. Every market a 50/50 chance of a draw-dawn (below the risk-free participant will assign a different value according to rate). Having a short put-delta position will lead us his state of knowledge and beliefs. If there are sell- with near certainty to buy back the asset at higher ers and buyers with different subjective valuations, prices. it might result in trades. These in turn might re- Figure 1 illustrates this. The x-axis shows the un- sultinobservedmarketprices. One shouldnote that derlying asset value, with x = 1 being the current the market price then does not necessarily represent spotprice. Thesolidline intheupper graphisalog- the subjective valuation of neither the buyer nor the normal distribution with an expected return equal seller3. to the risk-free rate (here 10%). The lower graph Secondly, even if we assume this awkward“under- shows the correspondingBlack-Scholesput-delta po- lying real distribution”, we find it difficult to fol- sition for a 110% strike. For this case it makes sense low the risk-neutral hedging argument, as the elim- inated term does not only contain uncertainty and 4Itisquestionablewhethertheconceptofarandomvariable can beconsistently defined [1]. Onecanarguethat “random- 2 A good pricing theory should be able to value an asset ness” is a result of insufficient information about the state of evenforaninside-trader. thesystem. Arandomvariableresultsthenfromuncontrolled 3SeeappendixE. (andhenceunknown)initialconditions. 2 0.6 Again, risk-neutral pricing gives us counter-intuitive risk-neutral log-normal 0.5 anotohreigr lloogg--nnoorrmmaall advisetoignoreourknowledgeoftheexpectedreturn. 0.4 Notethatthepointisnotwhetherweknowtheex- 0.3 pected return or not. The expected return is part of 0.2 whatwebelieveabouttheasset. Ifwearenotcertain 0.1 0 aboutitsvalueweshouldincorporatethisuncertainty 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1 1.2 1.4 1.6 1.8 2 x usingprobabilisticmethods,insteadofmodellingour 0 BS put delta for 110% strike knowledgeandthenthrowingpartofthemodelaway. -0.2 -0.4 3 An Alternative Approach -0.6 -0.8 -1 No “real” distribution InlinewiththeBayesian 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1 1.2 1.4 1.6 1.8 2 x interpretation of probabilities [1] we do not believe thatthereisanobjective“real”distribution. Historic data tells us what materialized, not what we should Figure1: Threelog-normalprobabilitydistributions believeaboutthefuture,andarguablynotevenwhat (expressing our subjective state of knowledge) with we should have believed (see appendix D). In fact, different drift rates and the corresponding Black- duetoselectioneffectshistoricdatacanbeextremely Scholes delta for a put with strike at the risk-free misleading —think ofhedge-fundmanagersshowing rate. Risk-neutral hedging suggests we use the same “consistent alpha” until they blow up. It appears deltaindependentlyofthedrift,i.e.forallthreecases. to be a common mistake to interpret historic data as representative of a “real distribution” for future returns as suggested by statistics. as the partial short position corresponds reasonably An objectionoftenraisedagainstthe Bayesianap- to the two possible outcomes. proachisitsrelianceonsubjectivepriordistributions. The two coloured lines in the upper graph are We wanttopointoutthatevenusinghistoricdatais two other log-normal distributions of the same (log- asubjectivematter—wejudgesubjectivelywhether return) standard deviation, but with different ex- the data can simply be extrapolated to the future. pected returns (drift). The blue graph represents a This is fine if one is aware of above selection effects case for which we are practically certain that the as- andrepresentativityissuesandjudges themtobe in- set price will have declined over the next year. For significant. If,however,thistreatmentisduetoanin- such a case it is clear that one would hedge a 110% terpretationofthe standardstochasticapproachand put by immediately shorting the full amount, as we above issues are ignored, one makes dangerous im- know that the asset will decline in value. plicit assumptions about the connection of the past Risk-neutral pricing would tell us though to price and the future. The markets have enough examples and hedge the position as if the expected return was of these, like misjudged risks on mortgages, credit actually the risk-free rate. If the blue graph repre- default swaps, and Ponzi schemes. In this context sents our state of knowledge,then this does not look pricing derivatives off a “risk-neutral” distribution like a good idea. appears like a safety precaution — too good things Thecasefortheredlineinfigure1issimilar. Here (drift) should be balanced by bad things, which are itisknownwithalmostcertaintythattheassetvalue notincludedinthe“realdistribution”ofthestandard will rise above the strike level, and hence that we approach. shouldnot havea shortposition atexpiry. It is clear Not everything is, and can possibly be in the his- that in such a case we would value the put worthless toric data. This data is conditional on where we are and we would also not hold a short delta position. nowanddrawingassumptionsaboutthefutureintro- 3 duces its own risks. This then has to be a subjective There is just an implied distribution, of which fu- process involving all information available5 and not tures determine the expected return. This implied just historic data. expected return is not necessarily the risk-free rate, but a return compatible with hedging expenses (and feasibility) (this is a well-known fact for commodi- Subjective and Implied Probability Distribu- ties withstoragecostslikeoil,butalsoforperishable tions We argue that every market-participant has agricultural products). By pricing options on such their own subjective probability distribution based assetsoffthe futures valueoneimplicitly usesthe fu- on the information available to him. Because peo- tures price as an expected return — now different to ple have different information available (and differ- the risk-free rate. ent levels of rationality when forming beliefs about thefuture)thedistributionsandhencevaluationsare subjective. Interaction of Spot and Future Markets We Thesedifferingvaluationsthenleadtotradingand first observe here that a future arbitrage trade does the observed market prices determine implied prob- not only move the futures price, but also the spot abilities — one can consider them the beliefs of the priceasassetswillhavetobeboughtorshorted. The market as an “organism”6. Futures imply expected neteffectisamovetowardsequilibriumofbothmar- returns for these implied distributions, but more de- kets. The less liquid market will adjust more than tailed implied distribution features can be extracted the liquid one7. from option prices (volatility smiles) [2]. Hence it is misleading to say that arbitrage does Hence we argue that there are only the beliefs of implyfuturesprices. Arbitragetradesmovespotand eachmarketparticipant(whichdonothavetobehu- futures marketstobe compatiblewithhedgingcosts. man,ascomputertradingillustrates)andanimplied (See figure 2 for an analogy from physics.) In effect probabilitydistribution(orforsparsedataratherim- this enforces an implied expected return compatible plied probabilities), which represents the “beliefs of with the hedging cost. For assets with no storage the market”. and transaction costs and available funding at the risk-free rate, this is the risk-free rate. But if the impliedexpectedreturnisthe risk-freerate,whereis Futures Futuresarearguablythemostsimplecon- the risk premium? tracts and they tell us directly the implied expected return. In the traditional approach it is argued that this 3.1 Risk and Risk Premium is true, but it is the expected return of the “risk- Part of the confusions seems to originate from the neutral” distribution (which obviously should be the mislabelling of uncertainty as risk. It is clear that risk-freerate)andthe“real”distributioncouldhavea there are situations where we are not certain about differentexpectedreturn,andinfactgenerallyshould the precise outcome, yet we are certain that we will have to allow for a risk premium. nothaveanadverseoutcome. Suchasituationisrep- We disagree and argue that there is nothing like a resented by the green line in figure 1 — here we are “real” distribution that exists objectively. almost certain not to lose money (with a long posi- 5 Interesting feedbacks ariseas people use historicdata as tion),butthereisasignificantuncertainty(standard information. If it is known how people use historic data this deviation) about the precise outcome. influencestheinterpretationofthehistoricdataitself. Wejust Should uncertaintythenattractarisk-premiumas wanttomentionheremomentum effects. 6 In fact, the economy as a system seems to satisfy most is for example assumedin Modern PortfolioTheory? criteria for a living organism. Even Darwinian evolution can be observed in the way business structures, political systems, 7 Note that the spot market isnot always the moreliquid andcommercialproductschange overtime. one. Oneexampleareilliquidgrainmarkets. 4 1.2 1.2-3-3 -2.5-2.5 -2-2 -1.5-1.5 -1-1 ppaarrtt-0.5-0.5iiaall ddiissttrrii 0 0bbuuttiioonn 0.5 0.5 1 1 1.2 1.2 1 1 1 1 0.8 0.8 0.8 0.8 pp 0.6 0.6 0.6 0.6 closed 0.4 0.4 0.4 0.4 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0 0-3-3 -2-2 -1-1 0 0 1 1 0 0 lloogg rreettuurrnn Figure 3: A distribution, appearingclose to normal, as one might estimate from historic returns. There appears to be a meanabove the risk-free rate (10%), which would traditionally be interpreted as a risk- closed premium for the uncertainty (variance or volatility). Figure 2: An example from physics illustrating how a common equilibrium is established due to interac- We would argue in two ways: Firstly, uncertainty tion. Under the influence of gravity two columns of isnotwhatwarrantsapremiumasitisaninsufficient liquids interact. The flow of liquids is the analogue descriptionofrisk. Andsecondly,therisk-premiumis to the flow of assets through time (e.g.being removed amisleadingconceptasitsuggeststhatthepremium from the spot market and stored for later disposal) ispartofthedistribution,butnottheriskwereceive betweenthefutureandspotmarkets. A“flowagainst it for. time” corresponds to short positions flowing forward We believe risk is best defined as the probability in time (like the travelling of ‘holes’ in semiconduc- of an adverse outcome as suitably defined for a cer- tors). If, for example, the left side corresponds to tain situation8. Hence the risk should be part of the the spot market and the boundary between the liq- distribution describing our beliefs about all possible uids represents the asset price, then the arrow on outcomes. If we are aware of possible negative out- toprepresentsassetsbeing carriedto the future, and comeswewilldemandcompensatingpossiblepositive the arrow at the bottom represents borrowed cash outcomes. positions to fund the arbitrage. The analogy could Figure 3 shows a partial probability distribution be taken further with friction and viscosity allowing which seems to have a significant “risk-premium” of slightly different levels on each side. about 15% above the risk-free rate of 10% (all log returns). Traditionally that would be seen as a com- pensation for the uncertainty (standard deviation) present. Figure 4 then shows the full distribution, which is actually a maximum-entropydistribution for a mean 8 Or through a probability distribution for adverse out- comes. 5 1.2 1.2-3-3 -2.5-2.5 -2-2 -1.5-1.5 -1-1 ff-0.5-0.5uullll ddiissttrrii 0 0bbuuttiioonn 0.5 0.5 1 1 1.2 1.2 sdcisatlreisbuwtiitohnsthoevesrhlaorge-spriinceisssauned) hoenneceshlooug-ldretluoronks.at Secondly, the log-normal probability distribution 1 1 1 1 is a normal distribution for log-prices, and hence it 0.8 0.8 0.8 0.8 is the maximum-entropy distribution for known vari- ance and mean. This means the distribution makes pp 0.6 0.6 0.6 0.6 the “least assumptions” besides what is known (the first two moments). So whether the actual log- 0.4 0.4 0.4 0.4 returns “are normal” or not is not the question — if we have only given the first two moments as a de- 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 scription of our beliefs then the normal distribution will be the right choice. 0 0-3-3 -2-2 -1-1 0 0 1 1 0 0 lloogg rreettuurrnn Thirdly, if we have no unique extra information (and historic data is available to everyone) then we might want to go with the “markets belief” of an Figure 4: The full distribution contains the risk expected return as priced in by the futures. in the left tail. This balances with the peak above the risk-freerateto give anexpectedreturncloseror Given above, the Black-Scholes pricing formulas equal to the risk-free rate. can easily be derived as the present value of the ex- pected pay-off under a log-normal probability distri- bution with a mean value of the risk-free rate (see equal to the risk-free rate and given values for the appendix B). This derivation is in fact considerably second, third, and fourth moment. Here we see that simpler than the stochastic differential equation ap- the “risk-premium” is really compensated by a fat proach10 — for example there is no need to invoke left-hand tail. The expected value contains both — Itoˆ’s lemma11. the risk-reward, if risks do not materialize, and the risk-penalty, if risks do materialize. Of course, that is not to say that we couldn’t do Hencewearguethat“realdistributions”(inpartic- better. Firstly, we might not be certain of the stan- ular log-normalwith a drift higher than the risk-free dard deviation, in which case our result incorporates rate) are the wrong way to incorporate risk-reward, a wrong sense of certainty in a parameter — see sec- as they incorporate a risk premium but do not ac- tion5.1below,where weshowthatanuncertainsec- count sufficiently for the downside-risk. ondmomentleadstoaskew. Secondly,wemighthave more information about the probability distribution, e.g., higher moments. Not using such information 4 Connection to Classical Pric- will of course be suboptimal. ing Ideas Sogiventheseconcerns,whyisBlack-Scholesdoinga reasonable9 job? To answer this question let us first 10It is interesting though that the Greens-function to the Black-Scholes partial differential equation is nothing else but note a number of facts. the log-normal distribution with the risk-free rate as mean. Firstly, one can argue that due to scale-invariance Sothewholeeffectofthedetour over thestochastic pdeisto (as the actual value of a share is meaning less — it eliminatethedrift. 11TheequivalentofItoˆ’slemmainaprobabilistictreatment 9 Andreasonabledoesnotmeangreat. Theobservedskew istrivial: Iftheprobabilitydistributionforln(x)isaGaussian showsthattheBlack-Scholespricingequationsareinsufficient. withmeanνandstandarddeviationσthentheexpectedvalue Seesection5.1,whichaddressestheseissues. See[3]forinter- of x is eν+σ2/2. If the expected value of x is known to be er estingcommentsonthehistoryandrelevanceofBlack-Scholes. thenwehavetosetν=r−σ2/2. 6 5 Applications 5.1 Unknown Variance 0.03 Letusassumeweaccepttherisk-freerateofreturnas our expected future asset return, but we are not cer- 0.025 tainaboutthesecondmoment(variance)foracertain date. How can we value an European option under 0.02 such circumstances? Inaprobabilisticframeworkthiscanbedealtwith prob 0.015 easily by marginalizing over the second moment pa- rameter (Black-Scholes ‘volatility’). Starting with 0.01 the definition of the derivatives value as the present value of the expected cash-flows12 we find 0.005 ∞ V = e−rt dxf(x)p(xI) 00 0.5 1 1.5 2 | volatility Z0 ∞ ∞ = e−rt dσ p(σ I) dxf(x)p(xσI) | | Z0 Z0 ∞ Figure5: Log-normalprobabilitydistributionforthe = dσ p(σ I)Vbs(r,σ), (2) standard deviation (Black-Scholes volatility). | Z0 where f(x) is the pay-off function, Vbs(r,σ) is the Black-Scholespriceforgivenrisk-freerateandsecond moment σ2 (‘variance’), and p(σ I) is expressing our | beliefs about the possible values of the (square-root of the) second moment. 1.4 Figures 5, 6, and 7 give a graphical example of above relationship. Figure 5 shows a probability dis- 1.2 tribution describing our beliefs about what the stan- dard deviation (Black-Scholes ‘volatility’) could be. 1 As the standard deviation is a positive quantity we 0.8 considerthelog-standarddeviationmotivatedbythe put price scale-invarianceargument[1]. Thesecondordermax- 0.6 imumentropydistributionforthestandarddeviation isthen,justasforthepriceintheBlack-Scholescase, 0.4 a log-normal distribution. The resulting put option 0.2 valuations and the implied volatility skew are pre- sented in figures 6 and 7. 00 0.5 1 1.5 2 2.5 3 One could now consider introducing additional rel strike “Greeks” for the parameters of the distribution of the standard deviation. If, as in the example, a log-normal distribution was used then the resulting Figure 6: Example put prices for certain standard Greeks follow directly from differentiating (2). deviation (green line) and for a log-normalprobabil- itydistributionforthestandarddeviation(blueline). 12 Weassumeherethattherearenodividendsandallother parametersareknown,i.e.expectedreturn,timetoexpiry,and risk-freerate. 7 where V is the value based on our subjective proba- i 0.65 bility distribution. We suggest to maximize the objective function 0.6 ξ(n ,...,n ) = Π Πm subject to constraints on 1 N − selected risk and possibly exposure measures (e.g.no 0.55 short positions). Two examples of possible risk con- straints are volatility 0.5 the probability of a loss (including initial costs) • 0.45 mustbe smallerthany (this measureis onlyde- pendent on the relative number of contracts) 0.4 if there is a negative final portfolio value, its ex- • 0.350 0.5 1 1.5 2 2.5 3 pected absolute value is less than z (expected rel strike value conditional on that there is a loss). In two dimensions this optimization can easily be Figure 7: The resulting implied probability skew done graphically. given the probability distribution of figure 5 for the second moment. 6 Conclusion 5.2 Exposure Management We criticised the stochastic risk-neutral pricing ap- proach for its lack of subjectivity and its mistreat- Let us assume we have a set of derivatives (on the ment of uncertainty as risk. In particular, risk- same underlying) we can invest in. Prices of these neutral pricing is founded on the questionable argu- aredeterminedbythemarket,andhencearecompat- ment that any drift is worth sacrificing to eliminate ible with the implied probability distribution p (x). m whatever uncertainty there is. Our valuations and associated risks though are de- In this paper an alternative approach was pre- termined by our subjective probability distribution sented which acknowledges that information and ex- p(xI). | pectationsaresubjective. Marketparticipantsshould Consider a portfolio consisting of n contracts of i use Bayesianprobabilisticreasoningto rationallyex- instrument i. The current portfolio market value is press their beliefs in terms of probabilities. Observed marketprices can be translatedinto im- N Πm = n Vm, (3) plied probability distributions, for which futures im- i i ply expected returns. i=1 X Givenno significantextrainformationit is reason- where Vim is the current market value of instrument able for market participants to adopt this expecta- i. The value of the portfolio to us is13 tion. We showed that if a market participant is ad- ditionally sure about the standard deviation then he N could rationally (due to a maximum entropy argu- Π= n V , (4) i i ment)useBlack-Scholespricingtosubjectivelyvalue i=1 X his position. If he is not sure about the standard 13 Here we make the simplifying assumption that Vi does deviation he would value his position according to a not depend onthe nj. This istrueformostinvestments, but skew. not in general. Consider the value of bottled water to you in We commented on possible applications to deriva- thedesert,whereyouaredehydrated. Thefirstbottlewillbe considerablymoreworthtoyouthenthe1,000’sbottle. tives exposure and risk management. Furthermore, 8 we considered the case of uncertain standard devia- to benecessary,becauseotherwisetherewouldbe no tion. Foralog-normalprobabilitydistributionforthe risk-premium. Hence the dogma that futures tell us standard deviation we illustrated how a “volatility- nothing about the “real” distribution. smile” was implied. While basedonsimple probabilisticprinciples,our B Deriving Black-Scholes from approach is quite a deviation from what are current standard methods in finance (and particularly in fi- the log-normal Distribution nancialmathematics)andwebelievethatitoffersan interestingdifferentperspectiveonfinancialmarkets. Let ν and σˆ2 be the firstmoment and secondcentral moment of the log-price probability distribution for sometimetfromnow,i.e.the distributionexpressing A Origins of risk-neutral Pric- our beliefs about future market levels. Having given ing nootherinformationourbestguessisthemaximum- entropy distribution for the log-price given the first All well known textbooks present the standard ap- two moments as constraints. This is a Gaussian dis- proachbased on stochastic differential equations, for tribution for the log-price, or the log-normal distri- example [4, 5]. bution for the price, which is given by Risk-neutralpricinghasitsoriginsinthestochastic 1 [ln(x) ν]2 approach to derivatives. Hence it is based on the p(x)= exp − . (6) idea thatthere is a “real”distributiondescribingthe xσˆ√2π ( − 2σˆ2 ) underlying return process (the “random variable”). Substituting z = ln(x)−ν we find In the Black-Scholes framework the “random pro- σˆ cess”oftheunderlyingassetpriceisdescribedbythe K 1 z(K) infinitesimal log-normalrandom price movements p(x)dx = e−z2/2 dz Z0 √2π Z−∞ dS =µSdt+σSdX, (5) = N([ln(K) ν]/σˆ), (7) − where S is the asset price, µ is the drift, σ is the where N(K) is the cumulative normal distribution volatility, and dX is a normally distributed random function variable. This is the only uncertain/random contri- N(x)d=ef 1 x dz e−z22. (8) bution to the price evolution. Hence it is argued 2π Z−∞ that a portfolio is “risk-free” if this term is elimi- Similarlyonefinds withz asaboveandtheinverse natedthroughasuitable(dynamic)hedgingstrategy, x = exp(σˆz +ν) (note the usual completing of the in which case the portfolio should earn cash returns. square in the exponent) Assuming this is done one arrives at the risk-neutral K z(K) exp(σˆz+ν) pricing formulas, which do not depend on the drift xp(x)dx = e−z2/2dz rate µ. Z0 Z−∞ √2π Thisconceptisextendedtootherdistributions,for ν+σˆ2 1 z(K) −(z−σˆ)2 whichthe risk-neutralmeasureis linkedto the “real- = e 2 e 2 dz √2π −∞ world” measure through a measure transformation, Z which sets the expected return to the risk-free rate. = eν+2σˆ2N ln(K)−ν σˆ . (9) σˆ − Thisthenleadstothenotionthattherearetwodis- (cid:18) (cid:19) tributions — the “real” distribution underlying the As K this gives the first moment m of x (ex- 1 processandthe “risk-neutral”distributionaccording pected→va∞lue) as towhichderivativesshouldbepriced. Itisimportant to understandthatthe “real”distributionis thought m =eν+σˆ2/2. (10) 1 9 Let us assume now that the first moment m is and ∆ the number of units of the underlying asset. 1 known to be equal to the present value x times the The portfolio value is then given by 0 risk-free growth factor, i.e. Π=V +∆S. (15) m =x ert. (11) 1 0 Differentiating with respect to the underlying asset Substituting from above and solving for ν (the first value S and demanding that the portfolio value is moment of the log-price) gives invariant gives ν =ln(x )+rt σˆ2/2. (12) ∂Π ∂V 0 − 0= = +∆, (16) ∂S ∂S For this value of ν let us define and hence ∂V ln K rt+σˆ2/2 ∆= . (17) d d=ef[ln(K) ν]/σˆ = x0 − (13) −∂S − 2 − (cid:16) (cid:17) σˆ Forexample,fortheunknownvariancecaseofsection and d d=efd +σˆ. 5.1thisgives(assumingthatp(σ I)isindependentof 1 2 | the spot level) The value ofan Europeanput with strike K is the present value of the expected cash-flow. Hence ∞ ∆= dσ p(σ I)∆bs(r,σ), (18) K − | V = e−rt dx(K x)p(x) Z0 p − Z0 where p(σ I) is the probability distribution for the = e−rt KN( d ) eν+σˆ2/2N( d ) standardd|eviationand∆bs(r,σ)istheBlack-Scholes 2 1 − − − delta for given standard deviation and risk-free rate. = e−rtK(cid:16)N( d ) x N( d ), (cid:17)(14) 2 0 1 − − − where we used (7) and (9) to evaluate the integral. D Real Uncertainties Given the second moment as an annualized variance σˆ2 = σ2t this agrees with the Black-Scholes pricing One might believe that generally probabilities are formula (for no dividends). about inferring a correct, but unknown value. For The calculation for European call and binary example,peoplemightaskthemselveswherethemar- put/call are very similar. ket will be on a certain date, and then see whether they guessed the “correct” value. The problemherearisesasitisimplicitly assumed C Reconstructing Hedging that the “correct value” exists objectively without Prescriptions being dependent on the actualbetting game and our associated behaviour. In this paper we emphasized that risk is not uncer- Letsconsideraspecificexample. Apparentlythere tainty. However, if one wants to eliminate uncer- wasalotterysysteminIrelandwherethe“luckynum- taintyonecanderivea“classichedgingprescription” bers” were assigned by a machine at the till. It so fromagivenpricingequation. This isverysimilarto happenedthatthelaterwinnerwasallowedbysome- theusualprocedure,exceptthatthepricinghasbeen oneelsetogoaheadandgethisnumbersfirst. Hence found independently. the winner claimed later that if that other person Let us assume we want to create a portfolio of a would have not let him go first, he would have not derivative and its underlying asset such as to have received the winning numbers. it momentarily invariant under asset price changes. This certainly would be true if the numbers would Let V(S) be our subjective value of the derivative have been drawn already at that point in time (and 10