ebook img

A History of Modern Criticism 1750-1950 Vol.2: The Romantic Age PDF

220 Pages·18.265 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview A History of Modern Criticism 1750-1950 Vol.2: The Romantic Age

OTHER BOOKS BY RENE WELLEK A HISTORY OF MODERN Kant in England The Rise of English Liurary History Criticism: J 750 -1950 Theory of Literature (with Austin Warren) BY RENE WELLEK The Romantic Age • JONATHAN CAPE Thirty Bedford Square, London CONTENTS FIRST PUBLISHED IN GREAT BRITAIN 195.5 Introductio_n 1. Friedrich Schlegel 5 2. August Wilhelm Schlegel 36 Second printing, November, z955 3. The Early Romantics in Germany: 74 Schelling 74 Novalis 82 W ackenroder and Tieck 88 Jean Paul 100 4. From Jeffrey to Shelley 110 5. Wordsworth 130' 6. Coleridge 151 .. 7. Hazlitt, Lamb, and ·Keats 188 8. Madame de Stael and Chateaubriand 216 9. Stendhal and Hugo 241 10. The Italian Critics 259 , 11. The Younger German Romantics: 279 Gorre s 279 'The Brothers Grimm 283 Arnim and Kleist 288 Adam M tiller 291 12. The German Philosophers: 298 Solger 298 Schleiermacher 3°3 Schopenhauer 308 Hegel 318 Conclusion 335 List of Abbreviations and Short Titles 342 PRINTED IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA Bibliographies and Notes 343 Chronological Table of Works 441 Index of Names 445 Index of Topics and Terms 455 v INTRODUCTION BY THE turn of the 19th century the romantic movements, at least ~;~any and England,.had definitely got under way. In Ger many the review written largely by the Schlegels, Das A thenaeum (1798-1800), is the crucial document; in England it is Lyrical Ballads (1798), by Wordsworth and Coleridge, to which Words worth added his theoretical Prefa ce in 1800. France seems to lag behind, since the French romantic movement is usually dated from the t;h!mph of Hernani (1830) or the appearance of Hugo's pref ace to Cromwell, three years earlier. Yet in 1813 Madame de Stael had expounded the classical-romantic distinction in De l' A lle magne, drawing on August Wilhelm Schlegel. In Italy the classical romantic debate started in 1816 under the influence of an article by Madame de Stael. But these recognized landmarks are some what deceptive: we shall see that even the Schlegels were not con scious of forming or founding a romantic school. The designation of contemporary German literature as romantic was due only to the enemies of the Heidelberg group (Arnim, Brentano, Gorres), which today is usually called the Younger or Second Romantic School. Jens Baggesen, a Danish poet residing in Germany, pub lished a parodistic Klingelklingelalmanach (1808) with the subtitle Ein Taschenbuch fur vollendete Romantiker und angehende Mys tiker. Arnim and Brentano took up with eagerness a term which was meant to be mere mockery. As far as I know, the first extended account of the new literary party of the ~o-called "Romantiker" can be found in the eleventh volume (1819) of Friedrich Bouter wek's monumental Geschichte der Poesie und Beredsamkeit. In England none ofthe romantic poets recognized himself as a roman ticist or recognized the relevance of the Continental debate to his own ti~e and country. In Italy and France one can speak of defi nitely "romantic" groups: in Milan after 1816, in Paris after 1824. But if we ignore the question of self-awareness and conscious 1 A HISTORY OF MODERN CRITICISM INTRODUCTION 3 2 advocacy of a romantic creed, I think _we ml!_~ !"ecogn~z~ th~ we classical distinction, but otherwise she and her opponent Chateau can speak of a general European romantic move~ent only if we briand can be described as adherents of the emotionalistic concept. t~ke a wide over-all view and consider simply the general rejection With Hugo there emerges in France for the first time a concept of oE• the neoclassical creed as a common denominator. In a history poetry which can be defined as symbolistic and dialectical. of criticism the rise of an emotional concept of poetry, the estab In Italy romanticism was largely a slogan recommending truth lishment of the historical point of view, and the implied rejection ancr contemporaneity in literature. The Italian romanticists antici of the imitation theory, of the rules and genres are the decisive pated what was iaterJ)roClaimed by the Junge Deutschland and signs of change, and these must be ascribed to the i8th rather than the early French realists. Foscolo, though no romanticist in his to the early igth century. :Qid.~rot_fillg Herde! are_lli~key figur~s. formal creed, must be described as close to Madame de Stael in There is no profound change in doctrinal positions and concepts of his emotionalistic concept and his grasp of the historical point of poeu-y between them and such "romantic" (in a more narrow view. Leopardi stands apart, with a profoundly personal, com sense) figures as Wordsworth or Hazlitt, Madame de Stael or pletely "lyrical" concept of poetry. But there is, I believe, no trace ·Foscolo. In a European perspective, in a history of critical thought, of the dialectical symbolistic view in Italy before De Sanctis. the technical romantic movements mean no radical change. What Thus one can speak of a romantic movement in criticism in two ev~ their importance· in literary politics, they did not, in them_ very different senses: in a wider sense it was a revolt against neo selves, make for a break in critical ideas. These had been formu classicism, which meant a rejection of the Latin tradition and the lated long before. adoptio~ of a view of poetry centered on the expression and com "--But within this very large movement there arose in Germany munication of emotion. It arose in the i8th century and forms a a new concept of poetry, symbolistic, dialectical, and historical, wide stream flooding au countries of the West. - which must be ascribed largely to Kant, Goethe, and Schiller. The ln a more narrow sense we can speak of romantic criticism as Schlegels, while hostile to Schiller, codified this view and gave it a the establishment of a dialectical and symbolistic view of poetry. turn which proved of great contemporary relevance. Germany, ft grows out of the organic analogy, developed by Herd~r and which in the early i8th century had passively received the main Goethe, but proceeds beyond it to a view of poetry as a union of doctrines of French neoclassicism, became the center of radiation opposites, a system of symbols. In Germany this view was in con- for critical thought. Especially did August Wilhelm Schlegel play stantdahger of becoming mystical and thus of losing its grip on a large role as its most effective propagandist. the aesthetic fact itself, but in the Schlegels and a few critics around The situation in England was, however, totally different: there them a satisfying theory of poetry was developed which guarded Jeff;ey a nd Wordsworth, though enemies, -developed further the its fences against emotionalism, naturalism, and mysticism and empirical, psychological view of poetry inherited from the i8th successfully combined symbolism with a profound grasp of literary century, and only in Coleridge can we speak of a dialectical and history. This view seems to me valuable and substantially true symbolistic view of poetry. This seems to have been imported from even today. We find it at that time, outside of Germany, only in Germany, though Coleridge nourished it by reading in the Pla two prominent critics: Coleridge and Hugo. tonic tradition, which lies back of the Germans. Coleridge, how For a modern theory of literature this view needs to be.described ever, remained isolated in his time and country, though he influ in all its implications and wealth of suggestions. We shall there enced Wordsworth and Hazlitt and later Carlyle. But both Words fore start with the Schlegels, whom we shall discuss not according worth and Hazlitt remained in the empirical psychological British to their .seniority but according to priority in ideas: first the tradition, and after Coleridge English criticism resumed its course younger Friedrich Schlegel, and then August Wilhelm. They de in the empirical tradition, almost unaffected by Coleridge's ideas. serve to be treated separately because they are distinct individual In France Madame de Stael was the importer of the romantic- ities with different points of view. We shall then take up the other 4 A HISTORY OF MODERN CRITICISM prominent German romantics: the philosopher Schelling, the mystical poet Novalis, the friends Wackenroder and Tieck, and finally Jean Paul, who seems to stand somewhat apart. They pro vide a body of thought and a definition of taste which can be con sidered as the background for Coleridge. But before discussing I: FRIEDRICH SCHLEGEL him, we have to turn to the minor English critics of the time from Jeffrey to Shelley, and to analyze Wordsworth's frequently mis judged position. After this, Lamb, Hazlitt, and Keats form a dis tinct·group held together by identical doctrines and a new method FRIEDRICH SCHLEGEL (1772-1829)-five years younger than his of metaphorical criticism which proved to be highly influential brother August Wilhelm (1767-1845)-was the more original and throughout the 19th century. In France we must couple Madame seminal mind of the two. His critical activity and effect precedes, de Stael and Chateaubriand in spite of their apparent antagonism, to a large degree, that of August Wilhelm. It is admittedly diffi and in the following chapter we shall confront Stendhal and Hugo, cult to decide questions of priority with exactness in the case of who both seem champions of the same romantic cause but hold two intimate brothers and friends, but there seems little doubt completely opposite views concerning the nature of poetry. The that the initiative was almost always Friedrich's. However, August Italians, stimulated as they were by both Madame de Stael and Wilhelm developed distinct critical theories of his own and can August Wilhelm Schlegel, follow naturally. We shall return to not be described as a mere echo of his brother, even though he Germany to describe the new developments there, which were not, served as codifier and popularizer of Friedrich's doctrines. One however, effective outside of Germany at the time under consid can hardly deny the greater effectiveness of August Wilhelm's ex eration: the mythic, collectivist concept of poetry in Jakob Grimm, positions, especially outside of Germany. His Vienna Lectures on the view of poetry as irony in Solger, an expressionist theory of Dramatic Art and Literature, which were delivered 1808-09 and art in Schleiermacher, the new concept of tragedy in Schopen published 18og-11, affected the course of critical thought very hauer, and the final synthesis of German aesthetic speculation in widely, especially after they had been translated into French ( 1814), the grandiose system of Hegel. In the Conclusion we shall look English (1815), and Italian (1817). It is also true that Friedrich briefly at the other minor countries and open a vista into the fu Schlegel was far less influential outside of Germany, since his con ture. version to Roman Catholicism in 1808 prevented him from re publishing most of his early writings and on the whole limited the appeal of his later work to the definitely conservative and Catholic world of the Restoration period. The Lectures on Ancient J. and Modern Literature, translated into English by G. Lockhart in 1815, was the only book of Friedrich's which attracted inter national attention. The early writings of Friedrich Schlegel, however, are of the greatest significance both for the history of romanticism and a general history of criticism. In close proximity to Schiller (whom he came to hate) Friedrich renewed the debate on ancients and moderns and developed from it the theory of the romantic which in his brother's version spread, literally, around the world. But Friedrich was not merely the propagandist of a catchword, the 5 6 A HISTORY OF MODERN CRITICISM FRIEDRICH SCHLEGEL 7 writer of literary manifestoes which would give him purely his self." 1 Greek poetry thus contains a complete collection of ex torical importance; he was also the author of a critical theory which amples of all the different genres and contains them in a natural anticipates many of the most urgent interests of our own time. In order of evolution. It serves both as a theory of genres and as a Friedrich's theory of the romantic there were contained and im picture of the whole cycle of the organic evolution of an art, as a plied theories of irony and myth in literature and the novel which kind of laboratory for theory, as "the eternal natural history of are pertinent even today. Moreover, Friedrich Schlegel reflected taste and art." 2 This evolution is conceived on the analogy of on the theories of criticism, interpretation, and literary history so biological evolution, in terms of growth, proliferation, blossoming, fruitfully that he can be claimed as the originator of hermeneutics, maturing, hardening, and final dissolution,3 an analogy which dur the theory of "understanding" which was later formulated by ing the 19th century received a great deal of impetus from Dar Schleiermacher and Boeckh and thus influenced the whole long winian evolutionism and led to such curiosities of literary history line of German theoreticians of methodology. These are solid as Brunetiere's evolutionary histories or John Addington Symonds' claims to fame, to which we must add Friedrich's pioneering work Shakspere's Predecessors in the Drama. Though this Greek evolu in Indic philology and philosophy and his wide-ranging histori tion must be thought of as somehow necessary and fated and the cal and practical criticism of Goethe and Lessing, Homer, Ca table of genres as complete, Friedrich Schlegel did not succumb moes, Boccaccio, and many other writers of almost all a,ges and na to the relativistic implications of his theory. When he said over tions. and over again that the "best theory of art is its history" 4 he did Friedrich Schlegel started out as a classical philologist. His am not mean the usual 19th-century historical relativism which is still bition was to become the "Winckelmann of Greek poetry," and crippling our present-day literary scholarship. He did not give up all his early publications, which include two books,• are devoted the task of evaluation or hide behind neutral history. In these early to this plan. But Friedrich Schlegel's studies of Greek poetry were writings Friedrich Schlegel found his standard in the prescriptive not, of course, antiquarian contributions to literary history nature, the ideal model of the great Greek classics; and late in his (though they display an astonishing learning for so young a man). life he came to impose more and more religious criteria derived As such they would necessarily be obsolete today and merit only from his Christian philosophy. But in his middle stage, which mention in a history of classical scholarship. Rather, he conceived clearly is the most interesting today, he recognized that the Greeks of literary history as so closely integrated with criticism that the cannot command the unique position he had claimed for them and history of Greek literature appeared to him both the nourishing that his theory of the relation between history and criticism must soil and the proving ground of an aesthetic. Greek literature, in be extended to the whole of literature without idolatry of any one these early writings, was considered uniquely suitable to such a nation .or age. He saw that the whole history of the arts and purpose, for Friedrich Schlegel not only saw the Greek works as sciences forms an order, one whole, or as he came to call it, an eternal models of perfection, as archetypes of poetry, but also "organism" or an "encyclopedia," and that this order is the "source thought of Greek literary history as natural, spontaneous, un of objective laws for all positive criticism." 6 For Schlegel literature disturbed by outside interference, and complete in itself. Greek thus forms "a great completely coherent and evenly organized culture is called "throughout original and national, a whole com whole comprehending in its unity many worlds of art and itself plete in itself, which merely by internal evolution reached its forming a peculiar work of art." 6 T. S. Eliot in "Tradition and -highest summit and, in a complete cycle, then sank back into it- the Individual Talent" has said substantially the same. But • Griechen und Romer (1797), which contains a long paper, "Ober Schlegel-differing fro~ the unhistorical Eliot-can say that he is das Studium der griechischeil Poesie," written in 1794-g5, and some "disgusted with every theory which is not historical" 7 and that smaller pieces; and Geschichte der Poesie der Griechen und Romer the "completion of every science is often nothing but the philo (1798), which, however, breaks off before treating Greek tragedy. sophical result of its history." 8 Schlegel thus rejects both unhis- 8 A HISTORY OF MODERN CRITICISM FRIEDRICH SCHLEGEL 9 torical theorizing and historical relativism. He recognizes that the author's secret intentions, which he pursues in silence and of which result of Herder's universal tolerance is the denial of any general we can never assume too many in a genius.'' 17 We should uncover standard of evaluation, in effect the abdication of criticism. The the deeply hidden, the unfathomable, and understand an author method of Herder to "contemplate every flower of art, without even better than he understood himself.18 These are dangerous evaluation, only according to place, time, and kind, would finally and paradoxical theories, with a measure of truth which has been lead to the result that everything must be as it is and was." 9 Also, exploited by much modern criticism far beyond Friedrich in later years Friedrich Schlegel rejected Adam Muller's similar Schlegel's dreams. Mostly, though, Schlegel suggests sound and concept of "mediating" (vermittelnd) criticism, since it abolishes sober principles of interpretation. He repeats the commonplaces the difference between the good and the bad and amounts to say of the historical spirit, the necessity of sympathetic entry into re ing, "Providence orders everything for the best, and everything mote times and countries, and he always stresses that one must had to come about as it did according to the philosophy, so dear know all the writings of an author in order to grasp their common to our contemporaries, of King Gorboduc: 'All that is, is.' " But spirit. In "art history," he understands, "one mass explains and illu the critical view cannot be simply absorbed by the historical be minates the other. It is impossible to understand a part by it cause books are not "original creatures.'' 10 These protests against self.'' 19 The construction and knowledge of the whole (of art and historical relativism are timely even today and were timely espe poetry) is the one and essential condition of all criticism.20 History cially in Germany, where in the later 19th century historical rela and criticism are one. Every artist illuminates every other artist: tivism destroyed criticism more thoroughly than in any other together they form an order. country. Schlegel attempts to describe what is needed in good criticism: Beyond formulating convincingly the relation between history "(1) a kind of geography of a world of art; (2) a spiritual and and criticism and stressing the aim of criticism as the "ascertaining aesthetic architectonics of the work, its nature, its tone; and finally of the value and nonvalue of poetic works of art," 11 Schlegel made (3) iis psychological genesis, its motivation by laws and conditions many fruitful suggestions concerning the nature of critical pro of human nature.'' 21 He speaks constantly of the whole: the spirit, cedure and interpretation. It is obvious that he derives from the the tone, the general impression. Mostly he thinks of criticism as a tradition o£ philology.12 He always stresses the share of philology "reconstructive" process. The critic must "reconstruct, perceive, in critical practice: "one cannot read out of pure philosophy or and characterize the more subtle peculiarities of a whole .... poetry without philology.'' 18 Philology means to him the love of One can say that one has understood a work and a mind only if words, the detailed attention to the text, "reading," interpreta one can reconstruct its course and structure. This profound under tion. A critic, he can say wittily, "is a reader who chews his cud. standing, if expressed in definite words, is called characterization He should have more than one stomach.'' 14 Reading or interpreta and is the actual business and inner essence of criticism.'' 22 Yet tion is always understood to be the right combination of micrology Schlegel has no use for the psychology of the reader, and he is and attention to the whole. "One should exercise the art of read- · strongest in his condemnation of the British psychological critics ing both very slowly in a constant analysis of the detail and more like Karnes. 23 He makes the sensible distinction between "fantas quickly, in one swoop, for a survey of the whole.'' u One should tics" (i.e. the theory of creation, of imagination) and "pathetics" (a not merely be sensitive to beautiful passages but be able to seize theory of the psychology of the reader, of the effects of poetry), but the impression of the whole, since "the first condition of all under comes then to the conclusion that "not much is gained for criticism standing, and hence also of the understanding of a work of art, so long as one wants only to explain the aesthetic sense in general, is an intuition of the whole.'' 16 instead of thoroughly exercising, applying, and forming it." 24 He Schlegel wants the critic to "spy on what he wanted to hide from therefore rightly remarks that "almost all judgments on art are our sight or at least did not want to show himself at first: on the either too general or too specific. The critics should look for the 10 A HISTORY OF MODERN CRITICISM FRIEDRICH SCHLEGEL 11 golden mean here in their own productions, not in the works of the existing, completed, even exhausted literature" but the organon poets." 2J5 of a literature which is just beginning to form itself. It is thus a Schlegel recognizes also the dangers of what we might call ex criticism which is not merely explanatory and conservative but clamatory criticism. "If many mystical lovers of art who consider all productive-at least indirectly so, by guidance, command, or in criticism dissection and every dissection a destruction of enjoyment stigation. His own criticism was surely "productive" in his great 30 were to think consistently, 'I'll be damned!' would be the best years, when he stimulated a whole emerging literature and helped judgment on the greatest work. There are critics who do not say to give it directibn. Instigating, directing, "producing" a new more, though at much greater length." 26 In general he describes literature will always be one of the tasks of criticism which cannot the aim of criticism as "to give us a reflection of the work, to com be reduced-as is fashionable today-to the preservation and municate its peculiar spirit, to present the pure impression in such winnowing of tradition. But "creative" criticism, the production a way that the presentation itself verifies the artistic citizenship of of another work of art, is an aberration, a needless duplication of its author: not merely a poem about a poem, in order to dazzle for a work of art, a blurring of necessary distinctions. a moment; not merely the impression which a work has made yes Schlegel's actual standards of evaluation and conception of terday or makes today on this or that person; but the impression poetry changed at least twice in his career: about 796, when he i which it should always make on all educated people." 27 This recog abandoned his "Graecornania"-apparently under the impact nizes the universal appeal any critical judgment makes, a claim largely of Schiller's treatise on Naive and Sentimental Poetry which Schlegel apparently found excessive at times: he would say and, more slowly and gradually, after 1801, when he moved toward merely that the "finished view of a work is always a critical fact" a purely religious conception which finally 1ed him to his conver and that it can make no other claims than its "invitation to every sion in 1808. But long before, poetry had become subordinated in body to seize his own impression just as purely and to define it just his mind to philosophy and religion. In the early writings on as strictly" 28 as the critic himself. At times, however, he can em Greek poetry, especially "Ober das Studiurn der griechischen brace the fallacy of "creative" criticism. "Poetry can only be Poesie," which, we must remember, was finished before Schlegel criticized by poetry. A judgment on art which is not itself a work could have read Schiller's treatise, Schlegel expounds a view of the of art, either in its matter, as presentation of a necessary impression contrast between the ancients and the moderns which in many in its genesis, or in its beautiful form and a liberal tone in the ways is very similar to Schiller's. It derives, of course, from spirit of old Roman satire, has no citizens' rights in the realm of Winckelmann, from Schiller's Letters on Aesthetic Education, and art." 29 But possibly the subclauses limit the demand of the main from Goethe, yet it is elaborated with sharp distinctiveness and clause: actually a work of criticism is artistic to Schlegel if it is a dogmatic assertiveness. The ideal of poetry is Greek poetry which precise reproduction of an impression or if it simply has the satiri is objective, "disinterested" (in the Kantian sense), perfect in form, cal polemical tone, the verve he loved and admired in himself and impersonal, pure in its genres, and free from merely didactic and others. moralistic considerations. But more important than this rehearsal "Polemics" is one of Friedrich ·schlegel's favorite words ,and of the familiar traits of Winckelmannian "classicity" is Schlegel's concepts. One of the functions of criticism is negative, the removal negative characterization of the moderns. of the false, the making of room for the better, and this is polemics Modern poetry is artificial, "interesting" (i.e. not disinterested, as practiced by writers like Lessing. "Polemics" is only the obverse involved in the author's personal ends), "characteristic," "man side of "productive" criticism, by which Schlegel means something nered" (in Goethe's sense, which contrasts subjective manner with much more practical and useful than "creative" criticism. He objective style), impure in its mixing and confusion of genres, im means criticism which we might possibly better call "incitory" or pure in its admixture of the didactic and philosophical, impure "anticipatory," criticism which is not the "commentary on an in its inclusion of even the ugly and the monstrous, and anarchic A HISTORY OF MODERN CRITICISM FRIEDRICH SCHLEGEL modern" and "not in the least romantic," while Shakespeare is the mains at least for communication in an illiberal frame of mind." 47 "real center and core of romantic imagination." The romantic Thus art demands the "liberal frame of mind," the power of the art thus can be found rather in the Renaissance and the Middle Ages, ist to raise himself above his own "highest." 48 "Irony is a clear con "in that age of knights, of love and fairy tales, whence the thing and sciousness of the infinitely full chaos," 49 of the dark and inexplica the word are derived." 40 But then the romantic is said to be not ble world, but it is also highly self-conscious, for irony is self-parody, a genre but an element of poetry, which may dominate or recede "transcendental buffoonery" which "rises above one's art, virtue, 50 more or less yet must never be totally absent. All poetry, Schlegel and genius." Irony is thus associated with "transcendental , concludes illogically, must be romantic. These passages contain the poetry," with the "poetry of poetry" which Schlegel finds in Pin-' essential distinctions of the romantic from the classical and the dar, Dante, and Goethe. Irony to Schlegel is objectivity, complete modern (i.e. pseudo-classical). But Friedrich Schlegel does not con superiority, detachment, manipulation of the subject matter. sider his own age romantic: he singles out the novels of Jean Paul Schlegel praises Wilhelm Meister for the irony with which the hero as the "only romantic products of an unromantic age." 41 Nor does is portrayed by Goethe, who seems to "smile down from the heights he expressly contrast the classical and the romantic (though he of his spirit upon his masterwork"; 51 and he looks for similar atti alludes to their possible union).42 The most influential formula tudes in Aristophanes, Cervantes, Shakespeare, Swift, Sterne, and tions of the great dichotomy belong only to his brother, August Jean Paul. Wilhelm, even though all its elements are in Friedrich Schlegel. There is no evidence that Schlegel found irony in the constant Schlegel's poetic ideal takes on much more concrete meaning if interference of the author in his work, in the deliberate breaking we examine his demands for irony, myth, and the mysterious, his of the illusion. Only in one fragment (No. 42 of the Lyceum) is conception of the novel, in fact his whole new hierarchy of genres. there an allusion to the Italian bufjo which might be so inter He does not call irony "romantic irony." All the early passages us preted.52 But Schlegel speaks there of poetry in general, not of the ing the term comment on the irony of Socrates, on his "sublime drama, and the reference to the buffo means only that the ironic urbanity," without any particular modern application.43 Only the author always smiles at' his imperfect medium just as the buffo review of Wilhelm Meister (1798) and the Gesprach ilber die laughs at his comic role. There is no recommendation of very old Poesie (1800) give it a meaning in the context of modern literature. devices of art: the playwright on the stage, the play within the play, I Irony is, in part, associated with Schiller's play-concept of art, the the author appearing in his own novel, which became such particu I Kantian view of art as free activity. We demand irony, "we demand lar favorites of Tieck and Brentano, E. T. A. Hoffmann and Heine, that the events, the people, in brief the whole play of life, should and came to be known as "romantic irony." At the time that really be conceived and represented as play." 44 Irony is associated Schlegel formulated his ideas on irony he did not know Tieck's with paradox. It is "a form of paradox. Paradox is what is at the comedies and he never considered them realizations of his ideals. same time good and great." 45 Irony is his recognition of the fact Goethe, Shakespeare, and Cervantes were his ironists, not his fel that the world in its essence is paradoxical and that an ambivalent low romanticists.• attitude alone can grasp its contradictory totality. For Schlegel • Schlegel's interpretation of irony has been argued over rather irony is the struggle between the absolute and the relative, the he;;ttedly, e.g. by Kathe Friedemann, "Die romantische Ironie," Zeit simultaneous consciousness of the impossibility and the necessity schrift fur Aesthetik, z3 (1919), 270-82; Carl Enders, "Fichte und die of a complete account of reality.46 The writer must thus feel am Lehre von der romantischen Ironie," op. cit., z4 (1920), 279-84; Alfred bivalent toward his work: he stands above and apart from it and Lussky, Tieck's Romantic Irony, Chapel Hill, 1932; and Oskar Walzel, manipulates it_a lmost playfully. "In order to be able to describe Romantisches (Bonn, 1934), pp. 73-93. I am convinced by Raymond an object well," Schlegel can say, "one must have ceased to be inter Immerwahr, "The Subjectivity or Objectivity of Friedrich Schlegel's ested in it . . . as long as the artist invents and is inspired he re- Poetic Irony," Germanic Review, :i.6 (1951), 173--91. A HISTORY OF MODERN CRITICISM FRIEDRICH SCHLEGEL Still, Schlegel's theory easily lent itself to a subjectivist interpre · the pantheism of Spinoza and the Orient, especially India, a hint tation; in his own novel Lucinde he certainly exemplified extreme which he later pursued systematically in his own Indic studies. subjectivism, playing with illusion, moral and artistic irresponsi But Schlegel apparently does not mean by myth merely a new bility. There is no contradiction between these two attitudes, cosmology or an exploitation of philosophical concepts; he thinks and in dialectical thinking one extreme easily passes into the of it, rather, as a system of correspondences and symbols. Myth other. is an analogue of the "wit of romantic poetry," as it is exemplified Friedrich Schlegel introduced the term irony into modern liter in the works of Cervantes and Shakespeare, which are full of "art ary discussion. Before, there are only adumbrations in Hamann. fully arranged confusion, charming symmetry of contrasts, marvel Schlegel's use of the term differs from the earlier purely rhetorical ous eternal alteration of enthusiasm and irony." Myth is some meaning and from the view of tragic irony in Sophocles which was thing he calls "an indirect mythology," 54 a new world view which developed early in the lgth century by Connop Thirlwall. Schle abolishes the course of logical reason and returns us to the "beau gel's concept was taken up by Solger, in whom it first assumed a tiful confusion of imagination, the original chaos of human nature, central position for critical theory and for whom all art becomes for which I do not as yet know any more beautiful symbol than the 'irony. Hegel and later Kierkegaard criticized Schlegel's concept, colorful milling throng of the ancient Gods." 55 However obscurely utterly mistaking it as a consequence of his adherence to the Fich this is phrased, the sense becomes clear if we see the passage in the tean philosophy of ego, as sheer opportunism, artistic and moral light of the other pronouncements on irony and the romantic. frivolity.* But in the actual texts there is no justification for such "Idealism" (i.e. Fichtean philosophy) means free play; life as play disparagement. One must realize, moreover, that irony for Schlegel and all art as symbolic. Schlegel does not yet use the distinction is only one element of modern self-consciousness and is combined between allegory and symbol drawn by Goethe and Schelling. He with very different requirements. thus can say, "All beauty is allegory" and "Because it is inex Among these, Friedrich Schlegel's demand for a new myth, an pressible, one can express the highest only allegorically." 56 Art, ironical, self-consciously elaborated, philosophical myth, is the therefore, is myth, symbolism, even "divine magic." 57 most striking. In the speech on mythology, which also forms a part More light is thrown on Schlegel's conception of poetry by sev of the Gesprach uber die Poesie (1800), Schlegel develops the thesis eral recently published fragments on beauty. Schlegel distinguishes -familiar today and still relevant-that modem literature lacks there between multiplicity, unity, and totality in beauty. The triad the support, the mother-soil, of myth. Classical and Christian my is derived from Kant's table of the categories of quantity,58 which thology had been used throughout the course of modern literature, he interprets as plenty, richness, and life in a work of art; harmony, and Germans preceding Schlegel, especially Herder and Klopstock, organization; and perfection or divinity. The first two criteria are had loudly called for the revival of Teutonic mythology, a return the well-known requirements of unity and variety, local texture to the sources of folk imagination. But Schlegel suggests a new and and general structure, or whatever we may call them today. The different mythology which would derive a new system of relation third category is clearly the same as the mythic or the infinite of ships, a "hieroglyphical expression of surrounding nature," 58 from other passages. At times, Schlegel has in mind simply the cosmic the new idealistic philosophy (Fichte) and the new physics (Schel quality of art which was familiar to Schiller and Kant. The "in ling's Naturphilosophie). The exact nature of the new mythology finite" is the morally sublime, the assertion of man's moral free is left vague in this manifesto. Schlegel suggests as further sources dom, his resistance to suffering in tragedy; 59 but mostly, with in creasing emphasis and frequency, poetry becomes a part of divine • Connop Thirlwall, "On the Irony of Sophocles," reprinted in Re creation, a smaller parallel to the work of art which is nature. "All mains Literary and Theological (London, 1878)., 3, 1-57. On Solger and holy plays of art are only distant imitations of the infinite play of Hegel see below, p. 299 £, 324. Soren Kierkegaard, Der Begrifj der lronie (1841); two Ger. trans., Munich, i929. the world, of the eternally self-creating work of art" 60-so runs an

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.