ebook img

A Forest of Symbols: Art, Science, and Truth in the Long Nineteenth Century PDF

321 Pages·2019·13.937 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview A Forest of Symbols: Art, Science, and Truth in the Long Nineteenth Century

A Forest of Symbols PPoopp__ppaaggeess__2211..iinndddd 11 88//1133//1199 11::3322 PPMM PPoopp__ppaaggeess__2211..iinndddd 22 88//1133//1199 11::3322 PPMM A Forest of Symbols Art, Science, and Truth in the Long Nineteenth Century Andrei Pop Z O N E B O O K S • N E W YO R K 2019 PPoopp__ppaaggeess__2211..iinndddd 33 88//1133//1199 11::3322 PPMM © 2019 Andrei Pop zone books 633 Vanderbilt Street Brooklyn, NY 11218 All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, including electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording, or otherwise (except for that copying permitted by Sections 107 and 108 of the U.S. Copyright Law and except by reviewers for the public press), without written permission from the Publisher. Printed in the United States of America. Distributed by The MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, and London, England Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Names: Pop, Andrei, author. Title: A forest of symbols : art, science, and truth in the long nineteenth century / Andrei Pop. Description: Brooklyn, NY : Zone Books, 2019. | Includes bibliographical references and index. Identifiers: lccn 2019005766 (print) | lccn 2019006411 (ebook) | isbn 9781942130314 | isbn 9781942130321 | isbn 9781942130338 | isbn 9781935408369 (alk. paper) Subjects: lcsh: Symbolism (Art movement) | Art — Mathematics. | Science and the arts — History — 19th century. Classification: lcc nx454.5.s9 (ebook) | lcc nx454.5.s9 p67 2019 (print) | ddc 700/.415 — dc23 LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2019005766 PPoopp__ppaaggeess__2211..iinndddd 44 88//1133//1199 11::3322 PPMM Contents Preface: Why Symbolism? 7 i Symbolisms in the Plural 17 ii Crises of Sense: The French Take on Edgar Allan Poe 51 iii Where Do We Come From? Symbolism’s Psychologistic Roots 99 iv What Are We? A Symbolist Picture Theory 141 v Where Are We Going? Consequences of Symbolism 189 Conclusion: Beyond Symbolism 235 Acknowledgments 241 Notes 245 Index 301 PPoopp__ppaaggeess__2211..iinndddd 55 88//1133//1199 11::3322 PPMM Figure P.1. Édouard Manet, Olympia, etching and aquatint (1865–67), New York Public Library. This plate was printed in Émile Zola’s 1867 book on Manet, subverting its insistence that paint handling was everything to Manet, subject matter nothing. PPoopp__ppaaggeess__2211..iinndddd 66 88//1133//1199 11::3322 PPMM preface Why Symbolism? What is art for? The question might be asked by a child. Children love to paint or sing or sculpt with putty, but they are often puzzled by what grown-up artists do: sell their work (“Why? I like my pictures and want to keep them for myself”), or work hard to install it in an art space, only to see it dismantled after a few weeks or months (“Why? I want to keep my pictures forever”). Mostly, artists talk about their work inter- — minably to patrons, dealers, and art writers. But how do those people know what art is about? The most pervasive theory of the art object in art history . . . was its conception as a medium of communication or expression. The object was construed within its communicational or linguistic paradigm as a “vehicle” by means of which the intentions, values, attitudes, ideas, political or other messages, or the emotional — state(s) of the maker or by extension the maker’s social and historical con- texts — were conveyed, by design or chance.1 The author of these words does not think that art objects actually func- tion as vehicles for what the artist has to say. But if they don’t, this matters not only to the art writer. It also concerns the artist, and any- one encountering art, whether in a museum, on the street, or on the Internet. If artworks are not vehicles for meaning, what else could have caused the scandal over Édouard Manet’s painting of the nude Olympia (1863)? Merely its appearance? The appearance of the oil painting is not that of the little etching Manet made for Zola’s book about his art (Figure p.1). But how on earth are we to chart the correspondence, and the divergence, between the two without taking meaning into effect? 7 PPoopp__ppaaggeess__2211..iinndddd 77 88//1133//1199 11::3322 PPMM A FOREST OF SYMBOLS I do not attempt an interpretation of Olympia and its variants here. But it is plain that depriving art of meaning deprives it of its power. Not all of its power, surely: artworks have many uses and effects. The German critic Walter Benjamin once said, “Dada hit the spectator like a bullet,” while Henri Matisse wanted his paintings to serve “like an armchair for the tired businessman.” But notice the metaphori- cal “like” in both quotations: it is in virtue of its meaning, its sense, what we make of it, that a picture may hurt us like a bullet or comfort us like squashy furniture. In this book, I call art that works mainly by virtue of its meaning symbolist art. This is a conceptual and not a historical definition. Yet there were artists and writers at the end of the nineteenth century who called themselves symbolists, and whose unifying trait, for all their political and aesthetic differences, was a concern with how art gets its meaning. This book is about them. The notion of art working in virtue of its meaning might seem either strange or banal. Is there really such a thing, and is it a dis- tinct historical phenomenon? Consider a passage from Mark Twain’s Adventures of Huckleberry Finn, published in 1884. Huck is trying, with little luck, to convince a skeptical Jim of the diversity of human languages: “Does a cat talk like a cow, or a cow talk like a cat?” “No, dey don’t.” “It’s natural and right for ’em to talk different from each other, ain’t it?” “’Course.” “And ain’t it natural and right for a cat and a cow to talk different from us?” “Why, mos’ sholy it is.” “Well, then, why ain’t it natural and right for a Frenchman to talk different from us? You answer me that.” “Is a cat a man, Huck?” “No.” — “Well, den, dey ain’t no sense in a cat talkin’ like a man. Is a cow a man? er is a cow a cat?” “No, she ain’t either of them.” “Well, den, she ain’t got no business to talk like either one er the yuther of ’em. Is a Frenchman a man?” 8 PPoopp__ppaaggeess__2211..iinndddd 88 88//1133//1199 11::3322 PPMM PREFACE “Yes.” “Well, den! Dad blame it, why doan’ he talk like a man? You answer me dat!” — Huck editorializes notoriously: “I see it warn’t no use wasting words you can’t learn a nigger to argue.”2 Twain liked the exchange so much that he entitled public readings from the book after the second half of Huck’s verdict. This ruffled feathers, more for the crudity of the epithet than for its racism.3 But a close look at the text belies these apparent last words. Huck, who had just argued with Jim about the story of King Solomon’s choice, thought he was offering logical argu- mentation: farmyard animals make different noises, so why shouldn’t people? For his analogy to work, Americans and Frenchmen ought to differ as do cats and cows; more precisely, they ought to differ in the same respect, that of belonging to the same species. That is exactly what Jim sees, and what he tries to show Huck: neither a cat nor a cow is human, and just to be thorough, they are not of the same species either (“Is a cat a cow?”). A Frenchman, being a man, hasn’t a cat’s excuse for communicating differently. The Socratic conclusion is that a Frenchman doesn’t speak differently from other people, in the respect that a cat or a cow does.4 There is call for belaboring the obvious point that Jim outsmarts Huck. For the moral and political insight that flows from the logical one, surely, is that Jim is as much a man as Huck. This is a lesson the book teaches, not tells. It does so by example, in the teeth of Huck’s conventional resistance to it. This can only take place though with the careful uptake of what the book offers: action and humor and characterization, but also argument and allegory. The silly logical bout is at the same time a moving symbol of intellectual equality. And so Huckleberry Finn can be profitably thought of as a symbolist artwork, though it doesn’t have the wan, moonlit ambiance of some of that art, an ambiance that Twain made fun of (Figure p.2). Besides being art history, then, this book is a history of ideas, because the concerns of symbolist painters and poets were shared to a remarkable degree by theoretical scientists of the period, especially by mathematicians and logicians dissatisfied with the empiricism 9 PPoopp__ppaaggeess__2211..iinndddd 99 88//1133//1199 11::3322 PPMM

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.