WHAT KIND OF CREATURES ARE WE? columbia themes in philosophy columbia themes in philosophy Series Editor Akeel Bilgami, Johnsonian Professor of Philosophy, Columbia University Columbia Themes in Philosophy is a new series with a broad and accomodating thematic reach as well as an ecumenical approach to the outdated disjunction between analytic and European philosophy. It is committed to an examination of key themes in new and star- tling ways and to the exploration of new topics in philosophy. All rights reserved Edward Said, Humanism and Democratic Criticism Michael Dummet, Truth and the Past John Searle, Freedom and Neurobilogy: Refl ections on Free Will, Language, and Political Power Daniel herwitz and Michael Kelley, eds., Action, Art, History: Engagement with Arthur C. Danto Michael Dummet, The Nature and Future of Philosophy Jean Bricmont and Julie Franck, eds., Chomsky Notebook Mario De Caro and David Macarthur, eds., Naturalism and Normativity Alan Montefi ore, A Philosophical retrospective: Facts, Values, and Jewish Identity Thom Brooks and Martha C. Nussbaum, eds., Rawl’s Political Liberalsim What Kind of CREATURES Are We? n o a m c h o m s k y Columbia University Press new york columbia university press Publishers Since 1893 new york chichester, west sussex cup.columbia.edu Copyright © 2016 Noam Chomsky All rights reserved Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Chomsky, Noam, author. What kind of creatures are we? / Noam Chomsky. pages cm. — (Columbia Themes in Philosophy) Includes bibliographical references and index. isbn 978-0-231-17596-8 (cloth : alk. paper) isbn 978-0-231-54092-6 (e-book) 1. Language and languages—Philosophy. I. Title. p106.c46 2016 401—dc23 2015021707 Columbia University Press books are printed on permanent and durable acid-free paper. This book is printed on paper with recycled content. Printed in the United States of America c 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 cover image : riccardo vecchio cover design : chang jae lee References to websites (URLs) were accurate at the time of writing. Neither the author nor Columbia University Press is responsible for URLs that may have expired or changed since the manuscript was prepared. CONTENTS foreword vii 1 | what is language? 1 2 | what can we understand? 27 3 | what is the common good? 59 4 | the mysteries of nature: how deeply hidden? 81 notes 129 index 147 FOREWORD Akeel Bilgrami t his book presents a lifetime of refl ection by a scientist of language on the broader implications of his scientifi c work. The title of this volume, W hat Kind of Creatures Are W e? , con- veys just how broad the implications are meant to be. They cover an impressive range of fi elds: theoretical linguistics, cognitive science, philosophy of science, history of science, evolutionary biology, metaphysics, the theory of knowledge, the philosophy of language and mind, moral and political phi- losophy, and, even briefl y, the ideal of human education. Chapter 1 presents, with clarity and precision, Noam Chomsky’ own basic ideas in theoretical linguistics and cogni- tive science (both fi elds in which he has played an absolutely central founding role), recording the progress achieved over the years but recording much more strenuously how tenta- tively those claims to progress must be made and how a very large amount of work remains to be done even in the most fundamental areas of study. Changes of mind over these years are also recorded, some of the most striking of which occurred only in the past decade or so. The chapter begins by motivating the question its title an- nounces, “What Is Language?” It behooves us to ask it because without being clear about what language is, not only will we not get the right answers to other questions about various spe- cifi c aspects of language (perhaps cannot even correctly frame those specifi c questions), but we will not get close to investi- gating or even plausibly speculating about the biological basis and evolutionary origins of language. A tradition that goes back to Galileo and Descartes recog- nized the most fundamental feature of language, which then viii got its most explicit articulation in Humboldt: “Language is quite peculiarly confronted by an unending and truly bound- less domain, the essence of all that can be thought. It must D R therefore make infi nite employment of fi nite means, and is O W able to do so, through the power which produces identity of E R language and thought.”1 Darwin, too, is cited as repeating O F this in a more elementary form in the context of evolution- ary concerns about language: “The lower animals diff er from man solely in his almost infi nitely larger power of associating together the most diversifi ed sounds and ideas.” It is worth noting that there are three fundamental features observed here by Humboldt and Darwin. First, the claim to an infi nite power residing in a fi nite base; second, the link of ideas with sound; and third, the link of language with thought. All of them are gathered in what Chomsky declares at the outset as the Basic Property of language: “[E]ach language provides an un- bounded array of hierarchically structured expressions that receive interpretations at two interfaces, sensorimotor for externalization and conceptual-intentional for mental pro- cesses.” The hierarchical-structural element speaks to the fi rst feature; the sensorimotor interface, to the second feature; and the conceptual-intentional interface, to the third feature. What will account for this Basic Property is a computa- tional procedure. The philosophical signifi cance of this is two- fold: a theory of language is necessarily a generative grammar, and the theory is necessarily about an object that individual human beings possess, internal to the individual subject and its mentality (i.e., intensional elements). It is not a theory about externalized utterances, nor is it, therefore, about a social phenomenon. The nomenclature to capture this latter distinction between what is individual/internal/intensional ix and what is externalized/social is I-language and E-language respectively. It is I-languages that alone can be the object of D scientifi c study, not E-languages. 2 And although such study is R O eventually to be redeemed in a biological account, until that W E eventuality the science captures the phenomena at a level of R O F abstraction from the biology and speaks at the cognitive level of the computational power that satisfi es the Basic Property. 3 A diff erent, more general, task is to discover the shared underlying features of all I-languages, which is determined again by the biological properties with which human beings are endowed (a theme whose wider signifi cance for cognition in general is discussed again in chapter 2). This more general task is undertaken with a view to discovering the biological en- dowment that determines what generative systems can serve as I-languages. In other words, what are the possible human languages? Chomsky then points out that as soon as the study of gen- erative grammars addressing the Basic Property of language was seriously undertaken, some surprising puzzles emerged, with far-reaching implications. One is the “structure depen- dence” of linguistic operations: in all constructions, in all languages, these operations invariably rely on structural dis- tance rather than on the computationally far simpler notion of linear distance. Language learners know this automatically, without instruction. There is support for this from evidence from experimental neuroscience and psychology. The result follows from the assumption that the order is simply not avail- able to the operations that generate the structured expres- sions that are interpreted at the conceptual-intentional in- x terface, for thought and organization of action. That follows, in turn, from the very natural assumption that I-languages are generative systems based on the most elementary computa- D R tional operation, which is order-free. These and numerous O W other considerations provide substantial evidence that linear E R order is ancillary to language, not involved in core syntax and O F semantics. The same is true of the various external arrange- ments of sign language, which is now known to be remarkably like spoken language in its structure, acquisition, use, and even neural representation. Presumably, these external properties refl ect conditions imposed by the sensorimotor system. The option of using linear order does not even arise for the lan- guage learner. Linear order and other arrangements are rel- evant to what is heard—that is, externalized—not to what is thought, which is interior. He then points out that these conclusions accord well with the little that is known about the origin of language. The sen- sorimotor system “appear[s] to have been in place long before language emerged,” and there seems to be little specifi c adap- tation for language. Cognitive properties of far deeper kinds than those possessed by apes, or presumably nonhuman homi- nins, are intrinsic to language. Apes have gestural systems ad-
Description: