ebook img

Ways a World Might Be: Metaphysical and Anti-Metaphysical Essays PDF

300 Pages·2003·1.3 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Ways a World Might Be: Metaphysical and Anti-Metaphysical Essays

WAYS A WORLD MIGHT BE This page intentionally left blank Ways a World Might Be METAPHYSICAL AND ANTI-METAPHYSICAL ESSAYS ROBERT C. STALNAKER Clarendon Press · Oxford GreatClarendonStreet,OxfordOX26DP OxfordUniversityPressisadepartmentoftheUniversityofOxford. ItfurtherstheUniversity'sobjectiveofexcellenceinresearch,scholarship, andeducationbypublishingworldwidein OxfordNewYork AucklandBangkokBuenosAiresCapeTownChennai DaresSalaamDelhiHongKongIstanbulKarachiKolkata KualaLumpurMadridMelbourneMexicoCityMumbaiNairobi SãoPauloShanghaiTaipeiTokyoToronto Oxfordisaregisteredtrademark ofOxfordUniversityPress intheUK andincertainothercountries PublishedintheUnitedStates byOxfordUniversityPressInc., NewYork ©RobertC.Stalnaker2003 Themoralrightsoftheauthorhavebeenasserted DatabaserightOxfordUniversityPress(maker) Firstpublished2003 Allrightsreserved.Nopartofthispublicationmaybereproduced, storedinaretrievalsystem,or transmitted,inanyform orbyanymeans, withoutthepriorpermissioninwriting ofOxfordUniversityPress, oras expresslypermittedbylaw, or under termsagreedwiththeappropriate reprographicsrightsorganization.Enquiriesconcerningreproduction outsidethescopeoftheaboveshouldbesenttotheRightsDepartment. OxfordUniversityPress,attheaddressabove Youmustnotcirculatethisbookinanyotherbindingorcover andyoumustimposethissameconditiononanyacquirer BritishLibraryCataloguinginPublicationData Dataavailable LibraryofCongressCataloginginPublicationData Dataavailable ISBN0-19-9251487 (hbk.) ISBN0-19-9251495 (pbk.) 13579108642 TypesetbyKolamInformationServicesPrivateLimited,Pondicherry, India. PrintedinGreatBritain onacid-freepaperby BiddlesLtd.,Guildford&King'sLynn In memory of Louis O. Mink Carl G. Hempel H. Paul Grice David K. Lewis This page intentionally left blank Preface Allbuttwoofthepapers included inthiscollectionhavebeenpreviouslypublished. Ithanktheeditors andpublishers for permissionto reprint them. Details of thesources are given on page xii. In most cases, the papers have been only lightly edited, but Chapter 3—a dialogue on impossible worlds—has been expanded in response to comments by DavidLewis, andpostscriptshavebeenadded toChapters5 and8onsometechnicalissuesdiscussedinthose papers. Thanks to Andy Egan for invaluable editorial assistance in preparing the papers and updating the references, and for adviceonmatters ofbothsubstanceand detail.Thanks toPeterMomtchiloffofOxford UniversityPress forhis good advice about the selection of papers, among many other things, and for his support. I can't thank by name all of the many teachers, colleagues, and students who have helped me to get clearer about the issues discussed in these papers, so let me thank them collectively, and mention just a few who stand out. Saul Kripke must take some of the blame for the preoccupation with possibilities that is evident in the papers in this collection, since I was first brought to appreciate the clarifying power of the framework of possible worlds in his seminar at Princeton in 1964–5 (where ideas about Wittgenstein on following a rule mingled with the ideas that were latertotakeforminNamingandNecessity).TheinfluenceofhisargumentsinNamingandNecessityonmyideasaboutthe relations between modal, semantic, and epistemological concepts will be evident throughout these papers, most explicitly in Part IV Four of the papers were originally written for festschrifts, and I am indebted to the philosophers celebrated in those collections – Paul Benacerraf, Ed Gettier, Ruth Marcus, and Sydney Shoemaker – all people with remarkable philosophicalminds whohaveinfluenced mythinking onmetaphysicalmatters throughtheirwork,theirexample,and philosophical discussion over the years. Thepaperonsupervenience(Chapter5)grewoutofametaphysicsseminaratMITtaughtjointlywithJudyThomson, and my thoughts about thisissue and others inmetaphysicshavebenefittedfrom her incisiveargumentsand analyses. Ned Block's insights into questions about consciousness and concepts have helped me to see many things I hadn't seen before. Collaboration with Ned, first on a seminar on consciousness, and then on a joint article (Block and Stalnaker 1999),was importanttomy understanding ofissues bothaboutmetaphysicaland conceptual possibility, and about viii PREFACE phenomenal consciousness. Some of the ideas in Chapters 10, 11, 12, and 13 have their source in that collaboration. Anyone who spends his or her time thinking and writing about philosophical problems develops, along the way, a clusterofprejudicesandpreoccupations,methodsandstylesofargumentthatconstitutes,onehopes,ageneralviewof things. Whereitcomesfrom and howitdevelopsis hard tosay, but theexamples provided byteachers and colleagues that we both follow and react against obviously play a crucial role in shaping our philosophical personae. The four philosophers to whose memory this book is dedicated played a particularly important role in my own philosophical development, boththrough thesubstance of theirideas and arguments, and by theforce of theirpersonalities. Letme say a little about each of them. Louis Mink was my main undergraduate teacher of philosophy at Wesleyan University. He was at the center of the intellectuallifeoftheuniversity, andhad manystudentswhowentontodistinguishedcareersinphilosophy. Louishad an insatiable intellectual curiosity, and showed us how to think philosophically about everything. With him I studied Kantand StAugustine, Collingwoodand logicalpositivism, thephilosophy of history and socialscience, among other things. He fed my ambivalenceabout metaphysics by getting me to appreciate both the richness of the philosophical traditionandthepowerofthelogicalempiricistcritique.Louishasalwaysbeen,for me,amodelofwhataphilosopher should be. I first encountered thework of C. G. Hempelin high school, browsingin James R. Newman's anthology, The World of Mathematics. His essays reprintedthere, ‘On theNature of Mathematical Truth’ and ‘Geometry and EmpiricalScience’ struck me as models of clarityand good sense, as they stilldo, and helped todraw me intophilosophy. WhenI got to graduate school I benefitted from his livelyseminars, patient and painstaking comments on my work, his writings on explanation, confirmation and concept formation, and most of all from his example of clarity of mind, intellectual integrity, and generosity. I was fortunate to be his student and teaching assistant. PaulGricewasnever myteacherordepartmentalcolleague,butIgottoknowhimwhenhemadeanextended visitto theUniversityofIllinois, whereI was teaching, in1970, and during a memorablesummer institute at Irvine in1971. I had earlier been able to attend just one of his William James Lectures, but I vividly remember the intellectual excitement of the occasion, the feeling that we were watching a great philosophical mind in action. Grice was an opportunistic and experimental thinker, eclectic in his methods and interests, following out lines of thought to see where they led him. But a coherent philosophical vision emerged – a view about the relations between language, thought, and action – that has greatly influenced my own way of thinking about these issues. PREFACE ix I began corresponding with David Lewis in 1968, when we discovered that we had developed,independently, similar theoriesofcounterfactuals,andwehadmanyfruitfulandenjoyablediscussionsovertheyears from thattimeuntiljust before his death in 2001. David was, of course, an unabashed metaphysician, and one might think that he was untroubledbythekindofmixed feelings aboutthesubjectthatIhaveexpressed, buthedid say, intheintroductionto his first collection of papers: ‘I should have liked to be a piecemeal, unsystematic philosopher, offering independent proposals on a variety of topics. It was not to be’ (Lewis 1983a: ix). In a sense, it was to be, for even though David's many philosophicalcontributions grewout ofhis metaphysicalsystem, and fit together withremarkablecoherence, he was carefultoshowus whenan analysis or an argumentwas detachablebyonewhodidn'tbuy intothewholesystem. His work was widelyapplied,bothwithin and outsideof philosophy, by researchers who wouldnothavethought that metaphysicscould berelevanttotheir work.Theinfluence ofDavid's work,and I hopeofhisexampleas well,willbe seen in every paper in this collection. Those who knew these four philosophers willagree that theywere radically different from each other in personal and intellectualstyle,buttheyareallparadigmcasesofphilosophers,andhadmuchincommon.Theyallhadapassionfor philosophy, and a focus onphilosophicalissues. Styleand method emergedfrom grapplingwith them. Whileeach had his own philosophical agenda, they were all adept at seeing things from other points of view, and were generous and effectiveinshowing others howtoadvancetheirownprojects. Theyallhad a senseofhumor and a senseoffun: they knew how to take philosophy seriously without taking themselves too seriously. They saw, and helped us to see, that philosophy is an activity that is both enjoyable and worthwhile. Cambridge, Massachusetts January 2003

Description:
Robert Stalnaker draws together in this volume his seminal work in metaphysics. The central theme is the role of possible worlds in articulating our various metaphysical commitments. The book begins with reflections on the general idea of a possible world, and then uses the framework of possible wor
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.