r I' I Ik I I f f f V - M f I I J - T an Edited by T C. Kline III and . Philip J. luanhoe _1 9/ 5 1« I H 2 Virtue, Nature, and Moral Agency in the Xunzi Edited, with Introduction, by T C. Kline III . and Philip J. Ivanhoe Hackett Publishing Company, Inc. Indianapolis/Cambridge Copyrighted malarial Copyright © 2000 by Hackett Publishing Company All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America 06 05 04 03 02 01 00 12 3 4 5 6 Cover design by Deborah Wilkes For further information, please address Hackett Publishing Company, Inc. PO Box 44937 . . Indianapolis, Indiana 46244-0937 www.hackettpublishing.com Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Virtue, nature, and moral agnecy in the Xunzi / edited with , introduction by T. C. Kline III and Philip J. Ivanhoe p cm. . Includes bibliographical references and indexes. ISBN 0-87220-523-1 (alk. paper) ISBN 0-87220-522-3 (pbk.) 1 Hsdn-tzu, 340-245 B.C Hs&i-tzu. 2. Ethics-China. L . Kline, T. C, 1966- II. Ivanhoe, P.J. B128. H7 V57 2000 181M12-dc21 99-052072 The paper used in this publication meets the minimum require- ments on American National Standard for Information Sciences-Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials, ANSI Z39.48-1984 @ Copyrighted malarial Contents Introduction ix Acknowledgments xix Note on Conventions and Abbreviations xxi 1 State and Society in the Xunzi: A Philosophical Commentary 1 . Henry Rosemont, Jr. 2 Ethical Uses of the Past in Early Confucianism: The Case . of Xunzi 25 Antonio S. Cua 3 Virtues in Xunzi's Thought 69 . Jonathan W. Schofer 4 Xunzi: Morality as Psychological Constraint 89 . Joel J. Kupperman 5 Mengzi and Xunzi: Two Views of Human Agency 103 . Bryan W. Van Norden Xunzi on Moral Motivation 13_5 David B. Wong 7 Moral Agency and Motivation in the Xunzi 155 . T C Kline III . 8 Xunzi and Zhuangzi 176 . David S Nivison 5L Theories of Human Nature in Mencius and Xunzi LSS D r Lmi 10. Does Xunzi Have a Consistent Theory of Human Nature? 220 Erie Hutton 11. Human Nature and Moral Understanding in the Xunzi 237 Philip J. Ivanhoe Contributors 25J Bibliography 253 Subject Index 259 Name Index 266 Copyrighted material Introduction Henry Rosemont Jr., began his 1971 article on the political and social , philosophy of Xunzi Kj with the following lament: "The study of early Chinese philosophy qua philosophy does not attract much attention in contemporary scholarly circles ... the philosophical depths of the classical texts are rarely plumbed anymore."1 He hoped that his study of Xunzi as political and social philosopher would take "a small step in catching up and reversing an untoward trend."2 Due to the work of scholars such as Rosemont, the "untoward trend" has been reversed and the study of Chinese philosophy is beginning to catch up to the rest of the field. Happily, we need not lament that Chinese philosophy is of no interest to contemporary scholars. Yet, much work remains to be done. This volume of essays, focused on Xunzi's ethical philosophy, continues the well-established trend of increased interest in and scholarship on early Chinese philosophy. Taken as a group, these essays support two related claims. First, contrary to what one might gather from orthodox Confucian criticisms of Xunzi's work, his writings are of great importance to the development of Confucianism and to the larger field of Chinese philosophy. There is even a case to be made for the claim that Xunzi's writings constitute the single most sophisticated philosophical explanation and defense of the Confucian point of view. Second, a careful consideration of these essays reveals Xunzi's writings to be of general philosophical interest and importance. Xunzi is not simply a significant Chinese philosopher, but an important world philosopher. His insights into various aspects of virtue, nature, and moral agency speak to our own concerns as well as to those of his second-century Chinese peers. These claims about the significance of Xunzi's work gain further support if we consider Xunzi and his writings in light of their influence on later generations of Chinese thinkers. In contrast to our limited biographical knowledge of many of the philosophers in early China, we have historical sources that record a good deal of information about the development of Xunzi's political and philosophical career,3 Xunzi, literally "Master Xun," was born in the state of Zhao j9 around 310 BC E during the Warring States period (403-221 B.C.E.).4 We know . . . little about his family or childhood, but through his writings, Xunzi reveals a thorough training in the arts of the aristocracy-hunting, archery, warfare, reading and writing, ritual activity, etc.-as well as an ix CopyrlghtGd malarial X Introduction education in classical literature. Since only wealthy families could afford an education of this sort we can safely surmise that he was born into a , relatively affluent family. In addition we know that Xunzi's public life , began quite early. At the age of fifteen he left his home in Zhao and , traveled to the state of Qi 9f in order to expand the range of his studies. In Qi he studied and later taught at the Ji Xia §[T Academy an , important center of intellectual life in early China that attracted scholars from many different states. While at the academy he would be , recognized as a leading thinker and teacher whose fame spread throughout and well beyond Qi. His distinguished place among the intellectuals of his time is attested to by his being appointed head libationer of the Ji Xia Academy-the honorary, highest-ranking participant in an official state ritual-an unprecedented three times. Xunzi's connection to the academy shows his active participation and leadership within the philosophical community at a time when philosophical discussion and the work of governing the state were thought to require and complement one another. This intellectual environment afforded him the opportunity first to study under the most distinguished philosophers of his day, to influence many of them through discussion and debate, and then to instruct a number of exceptionally talented students. Despite his recognition as a scholar and teacher, while in Qi, Xunzi did not hold any government position. Only after leaving Qi and moving to Chu 2i was he granted a political office. Eventually dismissed from office, apparently for political reasons, Xunzi retired and lived to see the unification of China under the Qin a process that to a large extent was accomplished through the work of his student Li Si $Wf. During his career, Xunzi wrote numerous essays on the pressing topics of the day. In his view, there were plenty of problems to be solved.5 The power and moral authority of the Zhou dynasty were in serious decline, and the rulers of various slates vied for political supremacy. Turmoil and intrigue, rather than harmony and benevolence, had become the predominant characteristics of those in positions of power. Neither the majority of the populace nor their rulers followed the ritual order of the early Zhou kings. Lacking the proper guides for moral cultivation, people were led to ruin by deceptive and misguided philosophies. Xunzi addressed these problems and described solutions that he believed would allow both individuals and the state to harmoniously follow the proper way of life, or Dao H. Like his Greek contemporary, Aristotle, Xunzi wrote on a wide variety of topics and organized them within the context of a larger, unified philosophical system. His sustained, philosophical arguments respond to CopyrlgWed matorlaJ Introduction xi the challenges of competing philosophical positions as well as explain and justify his own advocacy of Confucian ritual cultivation. As we have seen, Xunzi's views had a profound influence on his contemporaries, and this influence continued long after his death. For example, in the subsequent Han 9( dynasty, the great historian Sima Qian IQAMII recognized Xunzi's importance and included him, alongside the other leading philosophical figures of the past, in the biographies of his monumental Shiji aHitS "The Records of the Grand Historian." Many of Xunzi's most significant achievements can be seen in the development of the later Confucian tradition. He was the first philosopher to designate a textual canon, a canon that he believed was crucial to the process of moral cultivation. He included five works in the canon-1/ W "Rites," Yue M "Music," Shi & "Odes," Shu S . "History" and Chunqiu "Spring and Autumn Annals."b Over the course of time the Confucian canon would change, yet the set of texts established by Xunzi would endure as its central core. More importantly, the notion of a canon and its contribution to moral cultivation would remain a mainstay of the tradition.7 Along with the canon, Xunzi emphasized the fundamental role of the teacher in classical Confucian education. Although the importance of the teacher is implicit in the writings of Confucius and Mencius Xunzi provided explicit justification for the role teachers must play in moral cultivation. Moreover, he more thoroughly described the role of teachers and their significance in the process of guiding others through moral cultivation. Both his emphasis on the importance of teachers and his explicit justification of their role in moral education remained characteristic features of the later tradition. In addition, Xunzi expanded the understanding of tradition and argued for the necessity of both hierarchy and a unified set of standards with which to guide cultivation. All of these ideas became integrated into and came to be defining features of the Chinese imperial orthodoxy. It should be noted that Xunzi was not the only philosopher in the early tradition to discuss these issues, but he offered some of the most sophisticated analyses of these topics and was the only thinker to bring them together in a systematic fashion. For these reasons he may be identified as the most influential proponent of these ideas in the early Confucian tradition. As significant as these achievements are, Xunzi's most direct influence can be seen in the accomplishments of his students. It can be argued that it was through the influence of his students that many of the ideas described above became orthodox imperial beliefs and practices. Three of Xunzi's students are responsible for the transmission of extant Copyrlgmed matorlaJ xii Introduction classical texts. Fouqiu Bo 7?]iI5ffi conveyed the text of the Guliang Commentary RJUfl t0 t e Spring and Autumn Annals to Shen Pei $ i#. Zhang Cang 5JHI transmitted the Zuo Zhuan Mao Heng f learned the interpretations of the Odes from Xunzi and then taught them to his son Mao Chang :J|. Together the Maos wrote what became the orthodox commentary on the Odes. In each case, these stu- dents of Xunzi disseminated important classical texts, bringing them to the attention of Han scholars and transmitting'them to later generations. Xunzi's two most politically successful, as well as notorious, students were Li Si and Han Feizi As mentioned above Li Si , was an advisor to the Qin court and played an instrumental role in creating the policies that aided King Zheng of Qin 'Hil&i in his campaign of conquest that culminated in the unification of China and the founding of the first imperial dynasty-the Qin dynasty. Although King Zheng never directly employed Han Feizi, his ideas also contributed to the king's success. Han Feizi believed that the means of effective governing lay in developing bureaucratic methods for the control of political power. Like Xunzi, he wrote numerous essays explaining the techniques of governing and providing philosophical justifications for them. But, unlike his teacher, Han Feizi focused not on the power of ritual, moral cultivation, or the virtue of the ruler, but exclusively on the techniques for exercising and maintaining political power. After reading Han Feizi's essays, King Zheng implemented many of his policies during his campaign of conquest and in the administration of the subsequent Qin dynasty. Thus, taken together, the political skill of Li Si and the writings of Han Feizi constitute a central component in the foundation of the Chinese imperial state. In spite of the remarkable contribution these two students made in orchestrating the unification of China and the creation of the imperial bureaucracy, their success had a negative as well as positive impact on Xunzi's standing as a philosopher. For traditionally, the Qin dynasty was understood as a brutal and repressive regime. Since, from the Chinese point of view, teachers are responsible for the actions of their students, Xunzi was held accountable for the repressive measures used in the campaign that unified the empire and ensured the emperor's political power. Despite the negative impact of being associated with these two students, Xunzi enjoyed growing philosophical influence and reputation throughout the Han dynasty. Yet, by the early ninth century C.E., his public standing began to wane. Han Yu Kfi, a prominent scholar and literary figure of the late eighth and early ninth century C.E., in a short Copyrighted malarial Introduction xiii essay entitled Dxaun "Reading Xunzi "8 judges Xunzi to be inferior , to Mencius. According to Han Yu Xunzi's writings are "mostly pure , with minor defects," while Mencius' philosophy is "the purest of the pure."9 By the eleventh century, for a variety of complex reasons, philosophical interest turned toward Mencius and away from Xunzi. Primarily because Xunzi was recognized as opposing the Mencian interpretation of Confucius' philosophy the neo-Confucians of the Song , dynasty excised Xunzi from the grand Confucian narrative. As a result the writings of Mencius and not Xunzi were included in the , orthodox Confucian canon. Xunzi's claim that "human nature is bad" 'ft xing'e directly opposed Mencius' claim that "human nature is good" ttll xingshan and came to be regarded as a mark of Xunzi's inferior philosophical insight. Nevertheless, much of the rest of Xunzi's philosophy endured in practice even if publicly unacknowledged. Given this Mencian turn in the Confucian tradition, from the Song dynasty onward, scholars spent little time or effort studying Xunzi's philosophy.10 In the nineteenth and early twentieth century. Western writers and translators studying Chinese philosophy followed the orthodox neo- Confucian narrative. As a result, Xunzi was once again the subject of relatively little scholarly attention. James Legge, one of the most productive and influential translators of the nineteenth century, translated only a single chapter of Xunzi's writings. As part of the introductory material to his translation of the Mencius, Legge presented the Xing'e '|4 M chapter along with various other short essays by early Chinese philosophers who had written on the topic of human nature.11 In the late 1920s, Homer Dubs became the first person to publish a book-length study of Xunzi's philosophy-Hsiintze: The Moulder of Ancient Confucianism}1 This monpgraph was followed one year later by Dubs' selected English translation of Xunzi's writings.13 The publication of Burton Watson's partial translation in 1963 marked the next major event in Xunzi scholarship.14 Yet not until the mid-eighties was the second book-length study of Xunzi's philosophy published Antonio Cua's , Ethical Argumentation: A Study in Hsiin Tzu's Moral Epistemology.]5 In the last ten years scholarly interest in Xunzi's work has grown significantly. John Knoblock published, over a period of six years, his three-volume translation and study of the complete works of Xunzi.16 The publication of this full translation meant that the entire text was now accessible to non-Chinese readers. While Knoblock was publishing his complete translation, Edward Machle wrote a translation and study of the Tianlun chapter.17 And most recently, Paul Goldin has written a , CopyrlgWed matorlaJ xiv Introduction book on Xunzi's philosophy.18 Yet even taken together, these works , only begin to sketch the outlines of Xunzi's philosophical system . These observations concerning Xunzi and his influence argue for his importance to the field of Chinese philosophy Yet, what can be added to . support the additional claim that Xunzi is of philosophical interest to us-Western philosophers? To begin Xunzi writes sustained , philosophical arguments. His writings form a surprisingly consistent group of essays that, when taken together, form a complex and rich system of Confucian philosophy. The developed and systematic nature of his writings recommend him as a more accessible conversation partner for Western philosophers. In addition, Xunzi's broad knowledge of the early Chinese philosophical tradition outside of Confucianism makes his work exceptional. Although he devotes a great deal of time to criticizing rival philosophies, he adopts and adapts almost as much of their work as he condemns. For example, Xunzi criticizes Zhuangzi for being obsessed with Heaven and unable to understand either the importance of culture or the need for self-cultivation. Nonetheless, despite these criticisms Xunzi , adopts many aspects of Zhuangzi's conception of language and draws upon his understanding of moral psychology. In a similar manner in the , course of criticizing both Mencius a fellow Confucian, and Mozi H-F , , founder of a powerful, competing school of philosophy, Xunzi not only sheds significant light on important aspects of their philosophies but also deepens and sharpens his own work in the process. All these comments point toward Xunzi's involvement in an ongoing debate among early Chinese thinkers concerning the proper understanding of human nature, language, culture, and the need for or irrelevance of a ritual system of moral cultivation. He significantly adds to this debate by knitting together and defending a conception of human nature alongside a more complex theory of moral psychology and an understanding of moral cultivation and its connection to the mechanisms of tradition. While many of his views on this range of problems are distinctively Chinese-and uniquely Xunzian-the problems he confronts are recognizable and familiar to any philosophically-minded reader. These are our problems as well as his. We still grapple with questions concerning moral psychology and the proper role and form of education. We too worry about how to become better people how to cultivate , virtues in ourselves and inculcate them in others. We too try to explain the function of our social practices and describe their connection to tradition. Xunzi brings to these debates a rich conception of human nature, an element that is missing from many contemporary philosophical discussions of moral agency, and he is interested not only or even Copyrighted malarial