ebook img

Special Issue PDF

295 Pages·2017·6.61 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Special Issue

Editors–in–Chief Matthias Goldmann; Russell Miller; Jule Mulder; Emanuel Towfigh; Floris de Witte Senior Editors Matej Avbelj; Betsy Baker; Jürgen Bast; Gralf-Peter Calliess; Patrycja Dabrowska; Jen Hendry; Elisa Hoven; Agnieszka Janczuk-Gorywoda; Malcolm MacLaren; Stefan Magen; Nora Markard; Ralf Michaels; Anna Katharina von Oettingen; Emanuela Orlando; Niels Petersen; Christoph Safferling; Karsten Schneider www.germanlawjournal.com © Copyright 2000 – 2017 by German Law Journal, Inc. All rights reserved. ISSN: 2071-8322 / ISSNL: 2071-8322 Vol. 18 No. 05 Pages 1017-1308 01 September 2017 Table of Contents Special Issue Traditions, Myths, and Utopias of Personhood Guest Editors Toni Selkälä & Mikko Rajavuori Toni Selkälä & Mikko Rajavuori Traditions, Myths, and Utopias of Personhood: An 1017-1068 Introduction Table of Contents Table of Contents, cont. Visa Kurki Animals, Slaves, and Corporations: Analyzing Legal 1069-1090 Thinghood Lisette ten Haaf Unborn and Future Children as New Legal Subjects: An 1091-1120 Evaluation of Two Subject-Oriented Approaches—The Subject of Rights and the Subject of Interests Tuo Yu Approaches for Dealing with the “Natural Person” in 1121-1144 the Chinese Legal System: A Statutory Way and a Principled Way Jannice Käll A Posthuman Data Subject? The Right to Be Forgotten 1145-1162 and Beyond Ukri Soirila Persons and Things in International Law and “Law of 1163-1182 Humanity” Mikko Rajavuori Making International Legal Persons in Investment 1183-1228 Treaty Arbitration: State-owned Enterprises along the Person/Thing Distinction Susanna Lindroos-Hovinheimo There Is No Europe—On Subjectivity and Community in 1229-1246 the EU Table of Contents Table of Contents, cont. Alexis Alvarez-Nakagawa Law as Magic. Some Thoughts on Ghosts, Non-Humans, 1247-1276 and Shamans Mika Viljanen 1277-1308 A Cyborg Turn in Law? Table of Contents Special Issue Traditions, Myths, and Utopias of Personhood Traditions, Myths, and Utopias of Personhood: An Introduction By Toni Selkälä & Mikko Rajavuori Abstract Legal personhood continues to serve an important role in the legal system. The millennial distinction of persons and things, while often unarticulated, is an essential building block of all legal relations. This introduction to persons and things outlines the past tradition, draws on present myths, and construes a utopia of which the articles in this special issue will comment, clarify, and criticize.  PhD Candidates, University of Turku, Finland. Emails: [email protected]; [email protected]. We wish to thank Emanuel Towfigh and all the editors at the German Law Journal for their patience and support as well as wonderful attention to detail. We also thank Faculty of Law at the University of Turku, Turku University Foundation and eCoherence project for generous support, which enabled us to organize Persons/Things workshop. We are also greatly indebted to Gail Maunula for her wonderful proofreading help. Toni would further want to extend his gratitude to Law, Science, Technology & Society research group at Vrije Universiteit Brussel and Oxford Uehiro Centre for hosting him during the time of editing this special issue. And lastly, thanks to all the wonderful authors for making our work easy. The usual disclaimers, obviously, apply. 1018 German Law Journal Vol. 18 No. 05 A. Introduction “In what way is a thing not a person?” asks the bestial protagonist in Margaret Atwood’s short story Lusus Naturae.1 In all its apparent simplicity, this is also what the articles in this special issue on Persons/Things address. Why, what, and when does a person become a mere thing or a thing a person?2 What is the function of the legal distinction between persons and things, if any? The most canonical answer to this question argues that persons are ones who command a capacity to possess things—that distinction between the two is a means to establish property relationships. A person has rights and duties that allow her to do, to have, and to be,3 while a thing merely exists. How much does a person have to do and have in order to exist? Advancement in science and technology, together with globalization, has brought about many thorny issues for law and legal systems at large to solve over past decades. These issues share an intimate connection with the distinction between persons and things. The legal debates over the status of animals, corporations, unborn, non- biological machines, and nature have, for their part, made questions of personhood and personhood’s connection to rights topical. These and other things question what is the specific character enjoyed by natural persons, living human beings, that makes their actions significant and their rights legally enforceable in comparison to these other entities—the things. This introductory article, together with the articles of this special issue, argues for a gradual re-orientation of our understanding of personhood and, with that, our appreciation of things. Any inquiry into legal personhood is an attempt to constitute a tradition, a particular reading of the vast terrain of legal personhood. While the tradition of legal personhood is, in many ways, of more recent origin than its oft-quoted millennial heritage dating it to a Roman Law distinction between persons and things, persona and res, all attempts to justify a re-reading of legal personhood—ours included—commence with this tradition, contrived as it may be. In short, ours is an attempt through “the use of ancient materials to construct invented traditions of a novel type for quite novel purposes,”4 that is, an attempt to use legal personhood to argue that there exists a red thread connecting shamanism, fetuses, and corporations, among others, under the umbrella of a new-found tradition. In many ways, such an attempt clings onto a utopia of legal coherence where none might be found. Therefore, rather than arguing for a single, theoretically sound interpretation of legal personhood fit for the present, we trace two divergent paths and encourage following both. 1 See Margaret Atwood, Lusus Naturae, in STONE MATTRESS: NINE WICKED TALES 125, 130 (2014). 2 In what follows a person is an oft-used short-hand for a legal person but we occasionally variate and use terms such as legal personality or legal subject to refer to legal person. 3 See JEAN-PAUL SARTRE, BEING AND NOTHINGNESS 576 (1958). 4 Eric Hobsbawm, Introduction: Inventing Traditions, in THE INVENTION OF TRADITION 1, 6 (Eric Hobsbawm & Terence Ranger eds., 1983). 2017 Personhood: An Introduction 1019 One path leads to dilution of conditions formerly deemed essential for the existence of personhood. Examples of such practices are relatively commonplace, for one, the norm found in the European Data Protection Regulation equates rights with the existence of a living natural person, while simultaneously recognizing that DNA data of a deceased person can also constitute protected personal data.5 The other path evinces multiplication of entities endowed with personhood in an attempt to correctly attribute rights and duties. These are equally numerous as the examples of dilution of norms, as calls for robot personhood, artificial intelligence agency, or animal habeas corpus indicate. Rather than attempting to argue for convergence of these two different paths, we invite a diffractive reading of personhood “attuned to differences—differences that our knowledge-making practices make and the effects they have on the [personhood].”6 Alongside an invented tradition of ancient origin, there is a myth of unprecedented inattention fostered by authors writing on the topic of legal personhood. It is commonplace to argue that personhood is “grossly undertheorized”7 while at the same time participating in a lively debate over personhood across number of disciplines.8 This foundational myth constitutes the power of a proposed solution and its original, explanatory power by revealing the unprecedented inattention to personhood and, in doing so, making the author’s attention to it even more mystical in return.9 Closely resembling what Susan Marks calls the myth of the dangerous dark,10 the authors reveal their insights on personhood as a means to reveal something concealed within the dark folds of personhood that the inattention intensifies.11 Most often, the myth of unprecedented inattention highlights the fact that due to this inattention, a legal entity is discriminated against or not seen in the proper light. The present notion of personhood, grossly undertheorized as it might be, is a malign ideological 5 See General Data Protection Regulation 2016/679, 2016 O.J. (L 119); see also Opinion 4/2007 of the Data Protection Working Party on the Concept of Personal Data, 01248/07/EN WP 136) 22–23 (discussing the concept of personal data). 6 KAREN BARAD, MEETING THE UNIVERSE HALFWAY 72 (2007). 7 David Fagundes, Note: What We Talk About When We Talk About Persons: The Language of a Legal Fiction, 114 HARV. L. REV. 1745, 1768 (2001). 8 For other examples from upholding this myth, see, e.g., Stephen C. Hicks, On the Citizen and the Legal Person, 59 CINCINNATI L. REV. 789, 869 (1991); Anu Pylkkänen, Onko oikeuden henkilöllä sukupuolta?, 36 OIKEUS 147, 148 (2007) (asking to “develop an understanding of the legal person,” or noting how little discussion there is on what personhood entails” (author translation)). 9 See ROLAND BARTHES, MYTHOLOGIES 29 (1972). 10 Susan Marks, Four Human Rights Myths, in HUMAN RIGHTS 217, 231 et seq. (David Kinley, Wojchiech Sadurski, & Kevin Walton eds., 2013). 11 For a discussion with regard to fetal personhood and women’s rights, see Alejandro Madrazo, Narratives of Prenatal Personhood in Abortion Law, in ABORTION LAW IN TRANSNATIONAL PERSPECTIVE: CASES AND CONTROVERSIES 327 (Rebecca J. Cook, Joanna N. Erdman, & Bernard M. Dickens eds., 2014). 1020 German Law Journal Vol. 18 No. 05 lens that inverts the universal legal reality it is supposed to uphold to veer towards particularism.12 Re-adjusting personhood, the myth insists, will correct the wrongs endured. But could it be, as Marks suggests that “we should be more concerned with what happens in broad daylight, then perhaps the key myth is mystification itself—the myth of myths?”13 Here, we attempt to steer away from repeating the myth of unprecedented inattention. Rather, we seek to analyze the curious perception that often the very act of casting a light on inattention has been employed to perpetuate injustices attributed to that inattention. Thus, ours is an attempt to build a new tradition and construct a myth to uphold an ideological utopia of legal personality, or, alternatively, a readjustment of the present voluminous debate to address that which hides in the plain sight. This introduction is divided into two distinct parts. The first part provides a brief historical background of the conceptual development of legal personhood in the Occidental legal systems and their offspring, the Eurocentric international law. The latter part offers a more contemporary backdrop within which the articles of the present special issue operate as well as a modest proposal for a lens through which to reflect the emerging arguments for and against new categories of personhood. Even though these parts function independently, the theory formulation in the latter part builds upon the nuanced history of legal personhood. B. Building a Tradition The persons/things distinction in the law has many roots. Most Occidental normative orders, whether ecclesiastical or legal, presume existence of such a distinction. The Judeo-Christian maxim of humans’ dominion over nature, for instance, adheres to it. The most recurrent reference to a starting point of legal distinction between persons and things emanates from Ancient Roman Law. Gaius, in Institutiones, divides the realm of law into three categories: persons (persona), things (res), and actions (actiones).14 According to the system of the Roman law explained by Gaius, slaves as well as paterfamilias, head of the household, are humans (homo) but not necessarily persons (persona). They may be unequal humans, but humans nonetheless. Also, it is important to note that status as a person fluctuated throughout one’s life. Being a human did not prevent one from coming into possession of another. A human could be owned and traded much like a thing, but never become merely a thing. That same human could later gain the status of a person with all the rights and duties that followed. Thus, even though Roman law clearly marks the origin of distinction between persons and things that we still evince today—a fact both lawyers and philosophers agree on—present meaning given to this distinction is of much later origin. The Roman law might 12 For such a reading of ideology’s traits, see Paul Ricoeur, Ideology and Utopia as Cultural Imagination, 7 PHILOS. EXCH. 17 (1976). 13 Marks, supra note 10, at 232. 14 See GAIUS, INSTITUTIONES 13 (E.A. Whittuck ed., 4th ed. 1904). 2017 Personhood: An Introduction 1021 have contributed to what Roberto Esposito titles a dispositif of a person,15 as discussed, or alternatively we may consider that Roman law functioned as an example of Law for later scholars who have been decisive in formulating our present understanding of personhood and “thinghood .”16 I. An Enlightened Way to Make Persons Many of the histories of legal personhood share much more than a story of origin. The presence of Immanuel Kant, out of all Enlightenment philosophers, is one of these recurring features among legal scholars, even though the Enlightenment provided several formulations of agency, morals, and law.17 Kant’s argument for the inner worth of a person through her dignity, in contrast to a price carried by a thing, lays the groundwork for the modern concept of a legal person. As a consequence of embedding Kant’s formulation into law, the formerly porous border between person and thing is sealed. Where relatively late into the 18th century an animal on trial could readily be compared to a human, a thing in the Kantian system cannot be endowed with such dignity.18 For Kant, the distinction between a person and a thing relies ultimately on the capacity for autonomous agency manifested through moral action that creates a nexus between acts and persons. In short, working his way through Roman law and its distinction between persons and things, Kant established an additional condition for personhood, namely the capacity for moral action, which seemed to exclude not only non-humans but also a part of humanity outside its scope.19 While similar classifications had permeated both into law and into philosophy before Kant, it was precisely Kant’s formulation that gained widespread recognition and imitation, especially in the civil law tradition through the work of Friedrich Carl von Savigny.20 According to Savigny, rather 15 See Roberto Esposito, The Dispositif of the Person, 8 L. CULT. & HUMAN. 17 (2012); ROBERTO ESPOSITO, THIRD PERSON: POLITICS OF LIFE AND PHILOSOPHY OF THE IMPERSONAL (2012). 16 Christine M. Korsgaard, Kantian Ethics, Animals, and the Law, 33 OXF. J. LEG. STUD. 629 (2013); Rafael Domingo, Gaius, Vattel, and the New Global Law Paradigm, 22 EUR. J. INT’L L. 627 (2011). 17 See, e.g., JONATHAN ISRAEL, RADICAL ENLIGHTENMENT: PHILOSOPHY AND THE MAKING OF MODERNITY (2001) (discussing the influence of different stages of Enlightenment with different views regarding universality and what he titles Radical Enlightenment). For a materialist critique on the influence of this, see ANTOINE LILTI, 64 COMMENT ECRIT-ON L’HISTOIRE INTELLECTUELLE DES LUMIERES? SPINOZIME, RADICALISME ET PHILOSOPHIE ANNALES. HISTOIRE, SCIENCES SOCIALES (2009); ANN THOMSON, BODIES OF THOUGHT: SCIENCE, RELIGION, AND THE SOUL IN THE EARLY ENLIGHTENMENT (2008) (attempting to provide a counter-narrative). 18 The matter was not solely of having trials for animals, but also “the court, viewing insensate creatures as the equivalent of vulnerable minor.” See Esther Cohen, Law, Folklore and Animal Lore, PAST & PRESENT 6, 13 (1986). 19 As Christine Korsgaard argues, such a position is not sole or even the most likely interpretation of Kant’s formulation. Nevertheless, the way Kant’s tradition is perceived at present matters relatively little to past interpretation of his work by legal theorists. See Korsgaard, supra note 16. 20 But see Donald R. Kelley, Gaius Noster: Substructures of Western Social Thought, 84 AM. HIST. REV. 619, 645 et seq. (1979) (providing an interpretation of Savigny’s limited impact outside his work in Roman law). 1022 German Law Journal Vol. 18 No. 05 than receiving dignity and personhood through moral agency, human beings commanded innate value through the freedom they enjoyed, which ultimately led him to conclude that humans, and humans alone, enjoy legal capacity.21 Through these successive steps, an open category of a person was first tied to the capacity to act morally, which gained its legal formulation in an even more restrictive formulation that equated such capacity with humanity. While legal personhood, on a classificatory plane, granted all humans an inherent and equal recognition before the law, positive law limited or even fully negated these rights on a number of occasions. The most noted instances are related to the treatment of slaves, people in the colonies, women and children, and those deemed to be lacking mental capacity. This friction between general dictates of humanity and reducing humans to property is clearly played out in a late 18th century case of a slave brought from America to England.22 On arrival to England, Somerset—the slave—demanded to be set free, while Somerset’s master rejected his claim to freedom, referring to Somerset as his possession and asserted his rights of property ownership over the slave. The court accepted Somerset’s claim, but for reasons that were more tightly connected to the state of positive law than on general principles of humanity, “drawing a clear distinction between Somerset’s status as a human and his status as a legal person.”23 Thus, a denial of rights through concepts of individualism and property is the other facet of the Enlightenment tradition carried over to the present, demoting some individual human beings to a status closer to thinghood. It is an idea shared equally by Kant and Savigny, as well as Austin in the common law tradition.24 Austin formulated his own theory as an analytical will theory: for as long as there is a will, there is an entity that the law can command.25 It is this positive law tradition that also clearly expands the philosophical foundation of the distinction between persons and things further 21 See FRIEDRICH CARL VON SAVIGNY, 2 SYSTEM DES HEUTIGEN RÖMISCHEN RECHTS 60 (1840). 22 Somerset v. Stewart, (1772) 98 Eng. Rep. 499 (K.B.). 23 David J. Calverley, Legal Rights for Machines: Some Fundamental Concepts, in MACHINE ETHICS 213, 219 (Michael Anderson & Susan Leigh Anderson eds., 2011). Compare however to an account provided in JOHN T. NOONAN, PERSONS AND MASKS OF THE LAW: CARDOZO, HOLMES, JEFFERSON, AND WYTHE AS MAKERS OF THE MASKS (1976) highlighting the role of Blackstone in shaping the doctrine rather than considering the outcome merely a neutral enactment between positive law and more general principles of common law. 24 Richard Hartzmann, John Austin, in DICTIONARY OF LITERARY BIOGRAPHY: BRITISH PHILOSOPHERS 1800-2000 18–25 (2002); M. H. Hoeflich, John Austin and Joseph Story: Two Nineteenth Century Perspectives on the Utility of the Civil Law for the Common Lawyer, 29 AM. J. LEG. HIST. 36 (1985). 25 See JOHN AUSTIN, THE PROVINCE OF JURISPRUDENCE DETERMINED 5 (1832). 2017 Personhood: An Introduction 1023 towards contractual and utilitarian foundation,26 though such features were also perceived—at least by its critics—in the main treatises of the German historical school.27 The outline of the persons/things distinction embraced by Enlightenment thinkers and social theorists, lawyers and legal scholars included therein, embedded possessive individualism at the heart of Western normative enterprise.28 A legal person, equated with willfulness or a human holding interest, functioned as a basis also in social reforms pursued from the late 18th century to the mid-20th century. For a disparate range of thinkers, property served as a model of rights: a primary right among rights. The nexus of freedom and property made it entirely justifiable to demote or deprive rights for those lacking property.29 Thus, many of the first human rights declarations, in addition to limiting rights to men, limited political rights of those having large debts. These tensions between property and more general human rights are well illustrated through the example of auctioned children—and in some cases elderly and disabled—in Sweden and Finland in late 19th and early 20th century. In this practice, children that fell under the custody of a municipality were publicly auctioned to the lowest bidder, subjecting some auctioned children to slavery-like conditions.30 The practice—delegalized in 1918 in Sweden and 1923 in Finland—continued in Finland well into the 1930s, an era when supposedly everyone was granted equal rights according to the Finnish Constitution.31 A lack of means to economically support oneself allowed persons to be demoted to a category of chattel, while large property holdings garnered an increasingly independent status resembling that of a natural person. Corporations were the hallmark of the extension of rights and legal personality annexed to bodies of property. These were hardly novel developments in the late 18th and 19th century societies where Savigny, Austin, and others worked. The marked difference between earlier 26 See Hoeflich, supra note 24, at 44. 27 See Kelley, supra note 20, at 644. 28 It is contested to what extent the individual’s command or possession over herself was the very founding treatise of individualism and subsequent form of governance and of law. For debate, see, e.g., C.B. MACPHERSON, THE POLITICAL THEORY OF POSSESSIVE INDIVIDUALISM (1977); Quentin Skinner, The Ideological Context of Hobbes’s Political Thought, 9 HIST. J. 286 (1966), but few would, according to Peter Lindsay, Possessive Individualism at 50: Retrieving Macpherson’s Lost Legacy, 21 GOOD SOC. 132, 134 (2012) question the existence of such claims at the heart of Enlightenment perception of an individual that was later embodied as a person. 29 For the historical origins of this nexus, compare Morris R. Cohen, Property and Sovereignty, 13 CORNELL L. Q. 8, 18 et seq. (1927), with 2 HEINRICH AHRENS, COURS DE DROIT NATUREL OU DE PHILOSOPHIE DU DROIT. 7 et seq. (7th ed. 1875) (providing accounts stressing other foundational nexii, such as humanity). 30 See Sofia Lundberg, Child Auctions in Nineteenth Century Sweden: An Analysis of Price Differences, 35 J. HUM. RESOURCES 279 (2000); Elisabeth Engberg, Boarded Out by Auction: Poor Children and Their Families in Nineteenth- Century Northern Sweden, 19 CONTIN. CHANG. 431 (2004). 31 See FINLAND [CONSTITUTION] July 17, 1919, section 5 (containing general equality clause); Id., section 6(1) (protecting inter alia personal liberty).

Description:
Roman law explained by Gaius, slaves as well as paterfamilias, head of the .. existence of a European state as an actor and a “person” on the .. 81 HANS KELSEN, GENERAL THEORY OF LAW AND STATE 94 (1949). Personhood's expansion past the white, affluent, adult male had formerly
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.