T H E F R O N T I E R S C O L L E C T I O N Shyam Wuppuluri Giancarlo Ghirardi (Eds.) SPACE , TI M E A N D TH E LI M ITS OF HUM A N U N DER STA N DI NG Foreword by John Stachel and Afterword by Noam Chomsky 123 THE FRONTIERS COLLECTION Series editors Avshalom C. Elitzur Iyar The Israel Institute for Advanced Research, Rehovot, Israel e-mail: [email protected] Laura Mersini-Houghton Department of Physics, University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill, NC 27599-3255, USA e-mail: [email protected] T. Padmanabhan Inter-University Centre for Astronomy and Astrophysics (IUCAA), Pune, India e-mail: [email protected] Maximilian Schlosshauer Department of Physics, University of Portland, Portland, OR 97203, USA e-mail: [email protected] Mark P. Silverman Department of Physics, Trinity College, Hartford, CT 06106, USA e-mail: [email protected] Jack A. Tuszynski Department of Physics, University of Alberta, Edmonton, AB T6G 1Z2, Canada e-mail: [email protected] Rüdiger Vaas Center for Philosophy and Foundations of Science, University of Giessen, 35394 Giessen, Germany e-mail: [email protected] THE FRONTIERS COLLECTION Series Editors A.C. Elitzur L. Mersini-Houghton T. Padmanabhan M. Schlosshauer M.P. Silverman J.A. Tuszynski R. Vaas The books in this collection are devoted to challenging and open problems at the forefront of modern science, including related philosophical debates.In contrast to typical research monographs, however, they strive to present their topics in a manner accessible also to scientifically literate non-specialists wishing to gain insight into thedeeper implicationsandfascinating questions involved.Taken asa whole,theseriesreflectstheneedforafundamentalandinterdisciplinaryapproach to modern science. Furthermore, it is intended to encourage active scientists in all areas to ponder over important and perhaps controversial issues beyond their own speciality. Extending from quantum physics and relativity to entropy, conscious- ness and complex systems—the Frontiers Collection will inspire readers to push back the frontiers of their own knowledge. More information about this series at http://www.springer.com/series/5342 Forafulllistofpublishedtitles,pleaseseebackofbookorspringer.com/series/5342 ⋅ Shyam Wuppuluri Giancarlo Ghirardi Editors Space, Time and the Limits of Human Understanding 123 Editors ShyamWuppuluri Giancarlo Ghirardi R. N.PodarSchool(CBSE) Abdus Salam International Centrefor PodarEducational Complex TheoreticalPhysics Mumbai Trieste India Italy ISSN 1612-3018 ISSN 2197-6619 (electronic) THEFRONTIERS COLLECTION ISBN978-3-319-44417-8 ISBN978-3-319-44418-5 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-44418-5 LibraryofCongressControlNumber:2016950405 ©SpringerInternationalPublishingAG2017 Chapter15isdistributedunderthetermsoftheCreativeCommonsAttribution4.0InternationalLicense (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).Forfurtherdetailsseelicenseinformationinthechapter. Thisworkissubjecttocopyright.AllrightsarereservedbythePublisher,whetherthewholeorpart of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and transmission orinformationstorageandretrieval,electronicadaptation,computersoftware,orbysimilarordissimilar methodologynowknownorhereafterdeveloped. The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publicationdoesnotimply,evenintheabsenceofaspecificstatement,thatsuchnamesareexemptfrom therelevantprotectivelawsandregulationsandthereforefreeforgeneraluse. The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authorsortheeditorsgiveawarranty,expressorimplied,withrespecttothematerialcontainedhereinor foranyerrorsoromissionsthatmayhavebeenmade. Printedonacid-freepaper ThisSpringerimprintispublishedbySpringerNature TheregisteredcompanyisSpringerInternationalPublishingAG Theregisteredcompanyaddressis:Gewerbestrasse11,6330Cham,Switzerland Vox audita perit litera scripta manet, The thing heard perishes but the written word remains —Latin Maxim. Foreword First of all, let me thank Mr. Shyam Wuppuluri for his years of effort devoted to inspiring,assembling,andeditingthisvolume.Ratherthanattemptingtocomment onthepapersinit,Ishalltrytooutlinemyapproachtosomeissuesthatthereader may find helpful to bear in mind when reading these papers. Unfortunately, the concepts needed to discuss these issues are so interrelated that I have not found it possibletoprovideasimple,sequentialintroductiontotheseconcepts.Indeed,they are inextricably intermingled in my presentation. Everyhumancommunityisbasedonaninterrelatedcomplexoflaborprocesses that enable the community not just to survive but that, if successful, enable it to grow and thrive. Each such labor process involves three elements: the labor of a group of people using some tools to act upon the initial objects of labor (the “raw materials”). The goal of this process is action upon these initial objects in such a way as to produce final objects (the “finished products”) that will benefit at least some members of the community. But not all tools and initial objects are external to the members of the com- munity. Language—and other symbolic systems that language enables people to create—allows them to form conceptual systems, some of which in turn become intellectual tools that can be used to modify the initial conceptual systems and to create new ones. Inother words, notall labor need tobe manual.Justasimportant is intellectual labor. Like all forms of labor, intellectual labor starts from some object—in this caseaconceptualobject—andworksonthisobjectwiththeaimofmodifyingitto produceanewconceptualobject(seemypaper“ProblemsnotDisciplines”).There aremanytypesofintellectualtools(art,literature,religion,etc.)butmostimportant for the questions discussed in this volume are the scientific disciplines, including boththeso-callednaturalandsocialsciences(bettercalledthehumansciences—the Geisteswissenschaften in German). Why include the social sciences? As in all other forms of labor, a successful intellectuallaborprocessisultimatelytheresultofthecollectivelaborofmorethan one individual: knowledge is our name for such results. Rather than being an vii viii Foreword individual problem, as it has been treated in Western philosophy since the time of Descartes, the problem of knowledge is a social problem (see my paper Where is Knowledge?). And it should always be borne in mind that the ultimate goal of all intellectual labor is to provide additional resources to some human community for action upon the material world and, intended or not, to produce changes in the community itself. As noted already, in the case of intellectual labor the objects of labor are complexesofconcepts;andthecollectivelaboractinguponthesecomplexesisthat ofsomeintellectualcommunity.Whenitissuccessful,newknowledgeisourname for theresultsofsuch aprocessof intellectuallabor. And it isimportanttobear in mind that knowledge itself is indeed a process that will never end as long as intellectual communities continue to exist. So one should be suspicious of any proposed axiomatization of some realm of human knowledge, especially if it is accompaniedbyclaimsoftheclosureofwhatshouldbeanopen,unendingprocess. An important philosophical issue is the distinction between the conceptual objects that constitute our knowledge and the objects of that knowledge, and the relationbetweenthesetwo.Suchphilosophicaldoctrinesasconflictsasempiricism, rationalism, naturalism, materialism and idealism depend on the answer to this question. Suffice it to say that I regard the goal of action on the objects of knowledge as primary. The introduction of a new conceptual object, or the modi- fication of an existing one, must make clear its relation to some object(s) of knowledge.Inthecaseofphysicalconcepts,suchasspaceandtime,thismeansthat their definition must be accompanied by some account of the means by which an ideal measurement of this quantity can be carried out. Let me emphasize: I am not maintaining that it is meaningful because it is measurable;ratherthatbecauseitismeaningfulitmustinprinciplebemeasurable. No one has stated this lesson more eloquently than Gaston Bachelard: In order to embody new experimental evidence, it is necessary to deform the original concepts,studytheconditionsofapplicabilityoftheseconcepts,andaboveallincorporate theconditionsofapplicabilityofaconceptintotheverymeaningoftheconcept.…The classic division that separates a theory from its application ignores this necessity to incorporatetheconditionsofapplicabilityintotheveryessenceofthetheory(Laformation del’espritscientifique.Paris:Vrin.1938,pg.61;transl.byJ.S.). Like all tools, intellectual tools themselves may become the object of a labor process aimed at improving their effectiveness—indeed one tool may even be set aside totally in favor of some new tool. The prime example is relation between language, the first intellectual tool, and logic. Logic is a tool created for the improvementoflanguagewhenitisappliedtocertainsubjects.Indeed,oneshould rathersay“logics,”sincemorethanoneconsistentlogicalsystemmaybeemployed in the critical reconstruction of a language. So one might say that logic is about languageandlanguageisabouttheworld.Oftenthistwo-steprelationisreducedto a one-step relation: logic is about the world—a view I have criticized for decades [A]logicalwayshassomelanguageasitsobject.Themoreformalizedonewantsthelogic tobe,themoreformalizedthelanguagemustbe.…Sincealogicpresupposesalanguage, Foreword ix theobjectslogicstudiesmustbelinguisticobjects.Ibelieveintheexistenceofotherobjects whicharequiteindependentoflanguage;butsuchobjects,incontrast tolinguisticrefer- encestothem,cannothavealogic.Lestthisbethoughtamereverbalquibble,letmepoint out that someone who believed that all reality was fundamentally conceptual in nature couldmeaningfullyandnon-metaphoricallyspeakofthelogicoftheworld. Thedoctrinethatallrelationsarefundamentallylogicalrelationsandthatthereishenceno basicdistinctionbetweenlogicandontologyisnotunknowninthephilosophicalliterature. …Ithasevenbeengivenaname,“panlogism”…However,ifonedoesadoptthisposition, it should be done with full awareness, and not tacitly through acceptance of a certain approachtoquantumlogic”(excerptsfrom“DoQuantaNeedaNewLogic?”). I maintain that, in this respect, mathematics is similar to logic. Mathematical structuresdonotapplydirectlytotheworld,buttootherconceptualstructuresthat have been created to apply to some aspects of the world. Again this two-step relationisoftenshort-circuitedwiththeassertionthatmathematicalstructuresapply directlytotheworld(seeWhereisKnowledge?).Inthecaseofphysicalstructures, theeasiestwaytoseethefallacyofsuchanassertionisbylookingthequestionof units.Inordertoquantifyanyphysicalconcept,asystemofappropriateunitsmust be introduced; andit isonly theratio ofsome physical quantity toits unit that isa pure number, and the usual mathematical relation between two such physical conceptscanonlybeappliedtopurenumbers.Todefinethedistancebetween two points,onemustfirstspecifysomeunitofdistance,andthenumerical valueofthe distance between these points is then the ratio of that distance specified in these unitsdividedbythisunitofdistance. Givenasetofsuchprimary units,secondary unitsmaythenbecomputed.Forexample,inordertospecifythevelocityofsome object one must divide a spatial distance by a temporal interval; so units of space and time must first be specified. Finally, let me turn to the concepts of space and time. If we now consider the objects of the dynamical natural sciences, their objects themselves are processes (e.g., mechanical, electromagnetic, quantum, etc.). As long as the Newtonian worldview prevailed, it made sense to consider such processes as composed of a sequence of states, one for each value of the absolute time. But with the advent of the special theory of relativity, and even more the general theory of relativity, a viewpointbasedonstatesisnolongertenable.Theprocessesareprimary;andany introduction of a temporal sequence of states—to the extent that it is possible—is quite secondary and dependent on additional definitions. A number of theoretical physicists have emphasized the primacy of process, including Lee Smolin: Relativitytheoryandquantumtheoryeach.tellus—no,better,theyscreamatus—thatour worldisahistoryofprocesses.Motionandchangeareprimary.Nothingis,exceptinavery approximateandtemporarysense.Howsomethingis,orwhatitsstateis,isanillusion.It maybeausefulillusionforsomepurposes,butifwewanttothinkfundamentallywemust notlosesightoftheessentialfactthat‘is’isanillusion.Sotospeakthelanguageofthenew physicswemustlearnavocabularyinwhichprocessismoreimportantthan,andpriorto stasis(ThreeRoadstoQuantumGravity.BasicBooks,2001). x Foreword Toputitanotherway,thefour-dimensionalconceptofspace–timeisprimary,its possible division into three-dimensional space and one-dimensional time is quite secondary and depends on the introduction of additional concepts. What about time, the reader may object? Surely this is a primary concept. Here onemustmakeadistinctionbetweentwoconceptsoftimethatareoftenconflated: betweenwhatIhavecalledlocaltimeandglobaltime(see“AlbertEinstein:AMan for the Millennium”). To clarify what I mean by the concept of the local time betweentwoevents,Ioftendrawananalogybetweenthisconceptandtheconcept of the spatial distance between two places. It is well known that the distance between two different places depends on the spatial path between them. The shortestdistanceisalongthestraightestpathbetweenthem.Thelocaltimebetween two non-coincident events in space–time depends on the spatiotemporal path between them. That is the analogy; the difference is that the longest local time interval between thetwoeventsisalong thestraightest pathinspace–time has.As alluded to above in the discussion of units, it is the local time that is measured by clocks and the spatial distance that is measured by rulers (“measuring rods”). Clearly, when one speaks of two non-coincident events as “taking place at the sametime,”itcannotbetheconceptoflocaltimethatisinvolved.Indeeditishere that the concept of global time enters the story. When the Newtonian worldview prevailed, the additional concept of the absolute time provided such a definition oftheglobaltime.Twonon-coincidenteventseitheroccurredatthesameabsolute time or one preceded the other, and clocks measured this absolute time in a path-independent way. Once the concept of absolute time was abandoned, clocks measuredonlythepath-dependentlocaltime,andtwonon-coincidenteventsmight ormightnotbeconnectedbyatemporalpath.Givenaninitialevent,alleventsnot connectedtoitbyatimelinepathformanentireregionofspace–timethathasbeen called the elsewhere of the event. The concept of global time amounts to some definition of a three-dimensional slice of this four-dimensional elsewhere; and in general nothing physically significant can depend on this definition. The great divide between general relativity and all previous dynamical theories isthattheywereallbasedonfixedandgivenspace–timestructures.Alldynamical processes took place on the fixed and given stage provided by these structures. In contrast, general relativity has no such fixed structures. All space–time structures arethemselvesdynamicalentities,subjecttofieldequations.Sothatuntilasolution to these field equations is specified, no answers to questions about space–time structures can be given. As I have put it elsewhere: in all the rest of physics, “where” and “when” are parts of the question; in general relativity, “where” and “when” are parts of the answer. I do not expect the reader to uncritically accept my viewpoint on these issues; but hope that he or she will bear in mind the need for adopting some standpoint about them when confronting many of the questions discussed in this volume. John Stachel