N ROUTLEDGE STUDIES IN METAPHYSICS e ROUTLEDGE STUDIES IN METAPHYSICS o - D a v i d The Semantics and Metaphysics of Natural Kinds s o Edited by Helen Beebee and Nigel Sabbarton-Leary n i a n The Metaphysics of Powers M Their Grounding and their Manifestations e Edited by Anna Marmodoro t a p Freedom of the Will h y A Conditional Analysis s i Ferenc Huoranszki c s The Future of the Philosophy of Time Edited by Adrian Bardon Properties, Powers and Structures Issues in the Metaphysics of Realism Edited by Alexander Bird, Brian Ellis, and Howard Sankey The Puzzle of Existence S Why Is There Something Rather than Nothing? a m Edited by Tyron Goldschmidt u e l C Neo-Davidsonian Metaphysics . From the True to the Good W Neo-Davidsonian Metaphysics h Samuel C. Wheeler III e e le r From the True to the Good III Samuel C. Wheeler III www.routledge.com Neo-Davidsonian Metaphysics Much contemporary metaphysics, moved by an apparent necessity to take reality to consist of given beings and properties, presents us with what appear to be deep problems requiring radical changes in the commonsense conception of persons and the world. Contemporary metaethics ignores questions about logical form and formulates questions in ways that make the possibility of correct value judgments mysterious. In this book, Wheeler argues that, given a Davidsonian understanding of truth, predication, and interpretation, and given a relativized version of Aristotelian essentialism compatible with Davidson’s basic thinking, many metaphysical problems are not very deep. Likewise, many philosophers’ claims that common sense needs to be modifi ed are unfounded. He argues further that a proper con- sideration of questions of logical form clarifi es and illuminates metaethical questions. Although the analyses and arguments he gives are often at odds with those at which Davidson arrived, they apply the central Davidsonian insights about semantics, understanding, and interpretation. Samuel C. Wheeler III is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Connecticut, USA. Routledge Studies in Metaphysics 1 The Semantics and Metaphysics 5 Properties, Powers and Structures of Natural Kinds Issues in the Metaphysics Edited by Helen Beebee and of Realism Nigel Sabbarton-Leary Edited by Alexander Bird, Brian Ellis, and Howard Sankey 2 The Metaphysics of Powers Their Grounding and their 6 The Puzzle of Existence Manifestations Why Is There Something Edited by Anna Marmodoro Rather than Nothing? Edited by Tyron Goldschmidt 3 Freedom of the Will A Conditional Analysis 7 Neo-Davidsonian Metaphysics Ferenc Huoranszki From the True to the Good Samuel C. Wheeler III 4 The Future of the Philosophy of Time Edited by Adrian Bardon Neo-Davidsonian Metaphysics From the True to the Good Samuel C. Wheeler III First published 2014 by Routledge 711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017 Simultaneously published in the UK by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business © 2014 Taylor & Francis The right of Samuel C. Wheeler III to be identifi ed as author of this work has been asserted by him in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. Trademark Notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for identifi cation and explanation without intent to infringe. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Wheeler, Samuel C. Neo-Davidsonian metaphysics : from the true to the good / Samuel C Wheeler III. pages cm. — (Routledge studies in metaphysics ; 7) Includes bibliographical references and index. 1. Davidson, Donald, 1917–2003. I. Title. B945.D381W44 2013 110—dc23 2013011433 ISBN: 978-0-415-85728-4 (hbk) ISBN: 978-0-203-79810-2 (ebk) Typeset in Sabon by Apex CoVantage, LLC Contents Introduction 1 1 Davidsonian Truth and Its Consequences 13 2 Against Absolute Essentialism 39 3 Natures, Necessity, and Relative Essentialism 59 4 Kinds of Events 75 5 Modals and Conditionals 92 6 Properties, Propositions, and Facts 117 7 Future Contingents and Temporary Intrinsics 133 8 The Sorites and Davidsonian Innocuous Epistemicism 146 9 The Good 160 10 What We Ought to Do 183 Notes 207 References 229 Index 235 Page Intentionally Left Blank Introduction I RELAUNCHING THE DAVIDSON PROGRAM Donald Davidson’s program, as I encountered it in the late 1960s, was inspiring and exciting. It appeared that an account of logical forms, coupled with a semantics that eschewed metaphysics, would soon solve or dissolve many philosophical problems. Davidson’s thesis was that the fi rst step to dealing with a philosophical problem was getting the semantics straight. For instance, the fi rst step in answering the question “What things are good?” is fi nding out the logical form of sentences using “good.” The hope was that this kind of ground-clearing would enable real progress on the problems that did not, like the “problem of predication” or whether to believe in sparse or abundant properties, disappear with a proper understanding of semantics. Much of Davidson’s thinking was profoundly antimetaphysical, and the Davidsonian program was likewise antimetaphysical. Predication has no better account than “ ‘is a frog’ is true of an object just in case the object is a frog.” Truth is not correspondence to anything. Davidson’s account of meaning extended Quine’s ideas about radical translation to a theory of interpretation and an account of meaning without a metaphysics of meanings. Much of Davidson’s work continued the antiessentialist, anti- metaphysical logical positivist tradition, albeit without the dogmas, without the empiricism, and by and large without the scientism. Davidson himself implemented only a few parts of this program, and only suggested lines of thought for other parts of the program. His work on events, causation, adverbs, and the mind–body problem were actual concrete applications of his semantics. The project of fi nding logical forms for constructions of natural languages was being taken up most effectively by linguistic semanticists following the alternative path of Montague. 1 This side of recursive truth-conditional semantics was, from a Quinean point of view, completely shameless in invoking possible worlds, exotic functions, and the like. 2 The linguistic semanticists by and large accepted notions of presupposition, lexical meanings, and other notions that a Davidsonian 2 Neo-Davidsonian Metaphysics would eschew. Considering the scope of the original program, relatively little work was done trying to implement the Davidsonian program in the austere form that it began. Davidson thus left many important topics untouched. Davidson f ollowed Quine in not trying to give a semantics for modalities. 3 Unlike Quine, though, Davidson cannot just claim that there are no necessary truths. As long as some sentences using “necessary,” “possible,” and the like are true, these words must make some contribution to the truth-conditions of sen- tences. Other questions that the Davidson program in principle had to give a semantics were never addressed either by Davidson or his acolytes. For instance, the question of what propositions, properties, and facts might be has to have an answer, given that there are true affi rmative sentences using those terms. Even though Davidson has shown that properties play no role in understanding predication, that propositions as meanings of sentences are not necessary in semantics, and that facts play no role in providing an entity in the world for a sentence to correspond to in order to be true, still there are truths using those count-nouns whose truth-conditions need to be given some sort of account. Davidson had views about the objectivity of values and ethical notions, which appeared in scattered articles. The philosophical fi eld of ethics, though, was never one of his main interests. His earliest work was on decision-theory, and this was a continuing interest and topic of his writing. The project of connecting the theory of preference with a theory of what is good or what a person should do never got done. In sum, many parts of a completed Davidsonian program were never even begun. Part of the explanation is to be found in the resurgence of realism. Sometime after 1970, the majority of philosophers abandoned the whole logical positivist, antimetaphysical attitude toward philosophical problems that had culminated in Quine and then in nearly pure form, in Davidson’s program. The very intuitive arguments of Kripke (1980) convinced even Davidso- nians that appeals to natures made intuitive sense and had to be right. In my own case, I became convinced that Aristotle’s Metaphysics, especially Zeta, Eta, and Theta, was almost exactly right. There had to be natures of things and the d e re necessities that would be the consequences of such natures. So, at least some of Davidson’s disciples, and certainly very many philosophers who might have been attracted to the program, lost faith. Now in 2013, metaphysics is a thoroughly respectable fi eld, with very intelligent philosophers arguing pro and con about whether truth is an explanatory property, what mysterious bonding joins universals to particu- lars to yield facts, whether Ferraris are entities that persist or perdure, and the like. For instance, in the philosophy of mind property dualism competes with substance dualism. The Quinean–Davidsonian view that property ver- sus substance talk is misdirected talk about predicates is ignored. Introduction 3 Davidsonism and pursuit of the Davidson program has thus become a distinctly minority view. Davidson scholarship, while a burgeoning litera- ture, has become mostly exposition of the details of his actual writings on various topics, rather than an effort to carry out the program. I think this is a very large mistake, and that what has happened is that philosophers have forgotten Davidson’s basic insights about truth, predication, and interpreta- tion. An example of this forgetting is the continued proliferation of “logics” for the various modal predicates and tenses. 4 Quine’s notion of logic as pure structure and Davidson’s minimalist conception of semantics would put these “logics” in their proper place as theories of the truth-conditions of predicates. A couple of decades ago, I began to realize that the original program was not a dead end, but had been abandoned for inadequate reasons. A kind of forgetting had taken place, analogous to the forgetting that Kripke 5 recti- fi ed. The philosophical orthodoxies before Kripke’s 1970 lectures are a good example of the kind of forgetfulness that can occur in philosophy. As many people have realized, the intuitions Kripke was appealing to are essentially the same as those Aristotle was appealing to in Metaphysics Zeta, Eta, and Theta. Aristotle was responding to the challenge of Heraclitus against con- tinuants as well as to the inadequate defense of common sense from Plato. Aristotle’s distinction between essence and accident was a defense of com- mon sense. Kripke appealed to essentially the same intuitions. In Kripke’s case, of course, the frame of discussion was names and the conditions for their application. Very different philosophical environments generated very similar accounts of what it takes for this person to be the same over time or in different circumstances. To remind ourselves how much things have changed, remember that Quine (1953c) took the necessity for appealing to Aristotelian essences to be a decisive reason to reject the third grade of modal involvement. Aristotle’s insights about the necessities implicit in the idea of a lasting being were forgotten because Aristotle took the medium-sized objects of everyday life to be also the primary terms in which scientifi c explanation takes place. When it became clear that scientifi c explanations required something other than the objects of ordinary life, corpuscles or atoms rather than men and earth, a ll of Aristotle was abandoned, the insights along with the shortcomings. Something similar happened in a shorter time frame with Davidson’s thought. The main apparent defect in Davidson’s program was his rejec- tion of realistic metaphysics, the idea that nature is itself “divided at natu- ral joints.” It seemed to almost everyone that a realistic metaphysics was required in order to accommodate natural Aristotelian Kripkean intuitions, so that Davidson’s views could not be right. As with the rejection of Aris- totle in the seventeenth century, the rejection of Davidson’s program threw out the good with the inadequate. Just as Aristotle’s central insights about
Description: