ebook img

Natural law : the scientific ways of treating natural law, its place in moral philosophy, and its relation to the positive sciences of law PDF

138 Pages·1975·6.44 MB·English
by  
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Natural law : the scientific ways of treating natural law, its place in moral philosophy, and its relation to the positive sciences of law

Natural Law This page intentionally left blank G. W. F. Hegel Natural Law The Scientific Ways of Treating Natural Law, Its Place in Moral Philosophy, and Its Relation to the Positive Sciences of Law Translated by T. M. Knox Introduction by H. B. Acton Foreword by John R. Silber PENN University of Pennsylvania Press Philadelphia Copyright © 1975 University of Pennsylvania Press All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 32 Published by University of Pennsylvania Press Philadelphia, Pennsylvania 19104-4011 Published originally under the title: UBER DIE WISSENSCHAFTLICHEN BEHANDLUNGSARTEN DBS NATURRECHTS, SEINE STELLE IN DER PRAKTISCHEN PHILOSOPHIE, UND SEIN VERHALTNISS ZU DEN POSITIVEN HECHTSWISSENSCHAFTEN Library of Congress Catalog Card Number 75-10123 ISBN 0-8122-1083-2 Contents Foreword, by John R. Silber 7 Introduction, by H. B. Acton 9 Translator's Note 49 The Scientific Ways of Treating Natural Law, Its Place in Moral Philosophy, and Its Relation to the Positive Sciences of Law 53 Index 135 5 This page intentionally left blank Foreword Perhaps no other philosopher poses greater difficulties for his readers or promises greater rewards for diligent study than Hegel. In writing of the dividends to be derived from the "supreme thought-treasure" of Hegel's works, John N. Findlay has rightly praised Hegel's "stock of invaluable methodological principles by which one's own thought may be guided." Among these principles is Hegel's concern to preserve the unity of thought and reality, his concern to avoid the bifurcation of the abstract and the concrete, the ideal and the actual. Hegel's thought exemplifies a singleminded concern to avoid what Whitehead later would call "the fallacy of misplaced concreteness." Acutely aware of the philosophical and scientific tendencies to ignore the level of abstraction involved in our description of things, our habit of accepting some reduced and thereby distorted account of the object of thought in lieu of a genuine explanation, Hegel was concerned to comprehend—that is, to transcend a merely manipulative understanding of the world. He was contemptuous of accounts of the world that are merely possible, or that are incomplete and arbitrary descriptions of parts of the world distorted by isolation. He insisted on a philosophical account that could claim to be more than arbitrary, exhaustively concrete, and absolute in its comprehensive interrelatedness. Nowhere are these central concerns more clearly evidenced in brief scope than in Hegel's essay on Natural Law. Appearing at the very beginning of Hegel's prolific philosophical life, this essay provides a useful prologue, both in content and in methodology (which are for Hegel quite inseparable), to what follows. In this early essay are readily apparent Hegel's demonstration of the 7 8 FOREWORD incompleteness of both formalism and scientific empiricism and his insistence on a pure empiricism and a complete formalism, sustained by concepts that are genuinely absolute. Hegel's intentions stand out in bold relief as he struggles for the movements of thought by which to fulfill them. It is easier, I believe, to understand the full import of Hegel's mature formulations of his basic position when one attends their emergence in this brilliant formative work that, despite its brevity, reveals the comprehensiveness characteristic of Hegel's most extensive writings. The reader should find substantial assistance in the following introduction by H. B. Acton, which offers a useful commentary on the historical and philosophical background of the Natural Law and an exposition and analysis of many of its central issues. In section I, Acton places the Natural Law in its immediate historical context and then, in section II, traces Hegel's early philosophical development. In section III, Acton examines Hegel's treatment of natural law within the context of "pure" as opposed to "scientific" empiricism. Hegel's struggle with the formalism of Kant's theory of morality is discussed in section IV, and is followed in section V by a detailed discussion of the relation of the ethical life and the role of law in civil society that distinguishes Hegel's political philosophy from that of Fichte. In section VI, Acton illuminates Hegel's organic view of the ethical life and his conception of the individual as simultaneously a part and a whole of a society. A discussion of Hegel's view of history concludes the introduction. Acton's introduction should bring the Natural Law within the grasp of the beginning student of Hegel while providing a level of scholarship and insight to interest the mature philosopher. This splendid introduction is, lamentably, the last work of Professor Acton, who died soon after its completion. The translation, by Sir Malcolm Knox, Professor Emeritus of the University of St. Andrews, brings Hegel's ideas faithfully into English. His mastery of Hegel's thought has been indispensable to the success of this translation. John R. Silber Introduction I Hegel's essay The Scientific Ways of Treating Natural Law appeared in two consecutive parts (December 1802 and May 1803) of the Kritisches Journal der Philosophie.l This Journal ran from January 1802 until May 1803 and was edited by "Fr. Wilh. Joseph Schelling and Ge. Wilhelm Fr. Hegel" who between them wrote all the contents. The general aims of the Kritisches Journal are stated in an announcement of its forthcoming publication in the Literatur- Zeitung (December, 1801) and in the Introduction to the first issue entitled "On the Essence of Philosophical Criticism in General, and its Relation to the Present condition of Philosophy in Particular." The announcement refers to "the categorical nature of philosophy," to its "points of contact with the whole of culture" and to "the true rebirth of all sciences through philosophy," while the Introduction expresses hostility to any philosophical claims on behalf of "the healthy human understanding," by relation to which philosophy is said to inhabit "a world in reverse" (verkehrte Welt) .2 The "Idea of the Absolute" is presented as rejecting the opposition between idea and reality, between what should be and what is, and the opposition involved in the conception of "an infinite demand." The authors seem not only to be rejecting the philosophy and categories of Common Sense, but also to be hinting at disagreement with Kant and Fichte. Critical Philosophy, as Schelling and Hegel see it, rejects the categories of Common Sense and is no longer satisfied with any "polarity of the inner and the outer" or of "here and beyond." The dualism of Descartes is also attacked and said to be "a dualism in the culture of the modern history of our northwestern world, the decline of a whole mode of aging life, of which the quieter transformations of the public life of men and the noisy revolutions in politics and religion are only variegated manifestations." 9

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.