ebook img

Kant's Idealism: New Interpretations of a Controversial Doctrine PDF

278 Pages·2011·4.3 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Kant's Idealism: New Interpretations of a Controversial Doctrine

Kant’s Idealism The New Synthese Historical Library TextsandStudiesintheHistoryofPhilosophy VOLUME66 ManagingEditor: SIMOKNUUTTILA,UniversityofHelsinki AssociateEditors: DANIELELLIOTGARBER,PrincetonUniversity RICHARDSORABJI,UniversityofLondon EditorialConsultants: JANA.AERTSEN,Thomas-Institut,UniversitätzuKöln ROGERARIEW,UniversityofSouthFlorida E.JENNIFERASHWORTH,UniversityofWaterloo MICHAELAYERS,WadhamCollege,Oxford GAILFINE,CornellUniversity R.J.HANKINSON,UniversityofTexas JAAKKOHINTIKKA,BostonUniversity PAULHOFFMAN,UniversityofCalifornia,Riverside DAVIDKONSTAN,BrownUniversity RICHARDH.KRAUT,NorthwesternUniversity,Evanston ALAINDELIBERA,UniversitédeGenève JOHNE.MURDOCH,HarvardUniversity DAVIDFATENORTON,McGillUniversity LUCAOBERTELLO,UniversitàdegliStudidiGenova ELEONORESTUMP,St.LouisUniversity ALLENWOOD,StanfordUniversity Forfurthervolumes: http://www.springer.com/series/6608 · Dennis Schulting Jacco Verburgt Editors Kant’s Idealism New Interpretations of a Controversial Doctrine 123 Editors Dr.DennisSchulting Dr.JaccoVerburgt UniversityofAmsterdam VUUniversityAmsterdam DepartmentofPhilosophy FacultyofPhilosophy OudeTurfmarkt141–147 DeBoelelaan1105 1012GCAmsterdam 1081HVAmsterdam TheNetherlands TheNetherlands [email protected] [email protected] ISBN978-90-481-9718-7 e-ISBN978-90-481-9719-4 DOI10.1007/978-90-481-9719-4 SpringerDordrechtHeidelbergLondonNewYork ©SpringerScience+BusinessMediaB.V.2011 Nopartofthisworkmaybereproduced,storedinaretrievalsystem,ortransmittedinanyformorby anymeans,electronic,mechanical,photocopying,microfilming,recordingorotherwise,withoutwritten permissionfromthePublisher,withtheexceptionofanymaterialsuppliedspecificallyforthepurpose ofbeingenteredandexecutedonacomputersystem,forexclusiveusebythepurchaserofthework. Printedonacid-freepaper SpringerispartofSpringerScience+BusinessMedia(www.springer.com) Preface ThethemeofthiscollectionofessaysconcernsalongstandingissueinKantstud- ies, namely Kant’s controversial doctrine of idealism, most notably his notion of ‘the thing-in-itself’ and its distinction from ‘appearance’, which is Kant’s term for an empirically real object but of which he also notoriously says that it is a ‘mererepresentation’.Thequestionsurroundingthatsomewhatnebulousnotionof a ‘thing-in-itself’ is one of those perennial questions for Kant commentators, who aftermorethan200yearsofKantscholarshiphaven’tbeenovercomebyconsensus astohoweventointerpretKantianidealismandtheattendantdistinctionbetween appearanceandthing-in-itself,letaloneweighitsphilosophicalmerits. WhatisitaboutKant’sidealismthatstilloccupiesthemindsofsomanyKantians andnon-Kantiansalike?Whyandhowisitdifferentfromstandardidealismabout objects?HowdoKant’scommitmenttotheempiricalrealismofobjectsasappear- ancesandhisdenialoftheirultimatemetaphysicalrealitygotogether?Isittrue,as Hegel charged already early on in his critique of Kant, that Kant’s objects are not genuinely,objectivelyreal,butinfactonlysubjectivelyobjective?That,inHegel’s viewatleast,hisidealismisnotobjectiveenough? EversinceKant’scontemporaryJacobifamouslycomplained,inhisDavidHume (1787),thatthething-in-itselfpresentsanobstacletounderstandingthecriticalphi- losophy, many philosophers, sympathetic or not to Kant’s overall thought, have struggled with it. As Jacobi pointed out, without presupposing the thing-in-itself, which somehow causally affects us, ‘arouses sensations in us’, one cannot ‘enter thesystem’,butwiththepresuppositionit’simpossible‘toremaininit’forwithin Kant’ssystemit’snotpossibletogivejustifiablesensetotrans-phenomenalcausal- ity.Putdifferently,Jacobi’spointisthatKantneedsanargumentthatobjectsexist ‘outsideofusinthetranscendentalsense’,thusnot‘merelysubjectivelybutactually objectively’—which supposedly is the real relevant issue here. But such an argu- mentisunavailable forKant,Jacobiargues,sinceheclaimsabsoluteignoranceof knowledgeofthingsinthemselves(or,asJacobiputsit,the‘transcendentalobject’), whichisthemajorimplicationoftranscendentalidealism. Theideathatthingsinthemselvesaffectoursensibility,butneverthelessareinac- cessibleformindssuchasoursremainsamajorstumblingblockformanyreadersof Kant.AstrikingexceptionisHegel,whothought,withsomeexaggeration,thatthe v vi Preface easiestthingtograspinKant’sphilosophy waspreciselythething-in-itself.Hegel observeswithsimulatedwonder:“Wemustbequitesurprised[...]toreadsooften thatonedoesnotknowwhatthething-in-itselfis;fornothingiseasiertoknowthan this” (Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences, §44). But given that so many words have since been dedicated to grappling with the meaning of the thing-in- itselfanditsostensiblerelevanceforKant’scriticalthoughtthenotionisapparently notsoeasytograspasHegelhasusbelieve. However,asKarlAmerikshasaptlynoted,preciselybecause“[t]hedoctrineof transcendentalidealismissodifficult”,“oneshouldnotturnawayfromconsidering anyserioushypothesisthatmightshedlightonit”(InterpretingKant’sCritiques,p. 147). Indeed, widely varying and even deflationary interpretive approaches to ide- alism might together give us a better picture of possible avenues of approaching thiscontroversialdoctrinethatseemstobecentraltoKant’sphilosophy.Inthefirst partofthisvolume,whichfocusesmoregenerallyoninterpretingKantianidealism, ManfredBaumarguesthatKant’sfirstconcernintheCritiqueofPureReasonisnot idealismatall,butratherthefundamentalquestionregardingtheaprioricognizabil- ityofobjects.Insofarasidealismisconceivedofinthetraditionalsense,namelyin termsofanontologicalclaimregardingtheexistenceornon-existenceofobjects,it isnotpartoftheargumentintheTranscendentalAnalytic.Onewouldthusdobest nottoattachtoomuchimportancetothelabeltranscendentalidealism,alsobecause Kant himself uses it rather infrequently. Ido Geiger, on the other hand, seeks to defend the thesis that in the Critique of the Power of Judgment Kant formulates a superior version of transcendental idealism, which is no longer committed to the ideathatthingsinthemselvesasexistingentitiesunderlieappearances,asKanton hisreadingstillarguesinthefirstCritique.Havingwrittenextensivelyonthetopic, AmerikshimselfofferswhathenowcallstheModerateInterpretationofKant’side- alism, which one may see as his considered view on the topic. More in particular, in his essay Ameriks subjects the naturalist assumptions underlying a very recent readingofKant’sidealism,offeredbyRobertHanna,toacritique. Thearticlesinthisvolumearepartlybasedupontheproceedingsofaconference that was held at the University of Amsterdam, the Netherlands, in May 2008. The mainthemeoftheconferenceconcernedtherelationbetweenKant’stranscendental idealism and his transcendental logic—a relation that has been much neglected in the Kant literature. The reason for this appears to be the common but disputable conception that Kant’s doctrine of idealism and his discursive logic are wholly unconnected. MorethanfortyyearsafterthepublicationofP.F.Strawson’sclassicTheBounds of Sense, there is an ongoing interest among epistemologists in the potential for epistemology of a so-called transcendental theory of experience, which however dispenses with the ostensible speculative excess of Kant’s idealism. In some way or other, it is argued, the argument for a priori constraints for the experience of objects must be able to accord with unabashed naturalism about objects and, as Strawson forcefully argued in the latter part of his influential book, it is thus to be seen as quite independent of the doctrine of transcendental idealism. One of the reasons underpinning this view is the standard empiricist assumption that the Preface vii analysis of knowledge has nothing in common with the forms of logic. This goes ofcourseagainstKant’sexplicitclaimthatthecategoriesofexperiencecorrespond to,andarederivablefrom,theformsofjudgment.Moreimportantly,itobstructsan understandingoftherelevanceoftranscendentalinquiryforKant’scriticalproject andthusanunderstandingofhisidealismascontributingtowhatheasserts,inthe prefaceofthesecondeditionoftheCritiqueofPureReason,isa“changeintheway ofthinking”(Bxvi;emphasisadded).Itwouldappearthereforethattranscendental philosophycannotconcernmerelyatheoryofknowledgeastraditionallyconceived. Insomefurtherspecifiableway,itmusthavetodowiththelogicofthoughtitself, notjustthelogicofexperience. More often it is claimed that Kant’s idealism is intrinsically linked up with his controversial views on space and time, more in particular his notorious view that spatiotemporal objects are not ultimately real, and that consequently idealism can easily be detached from his views on the conceptual requirements for knowledge. However, it is debatable whether Kant’s distinctive transcendental logic regarding the cognitive structure of experience can indeed be separated from idealism about spatiotemporalobjects.WhereasintheearlierliteraturetherelationbetweenKant’s aesthetics and idealism has been extensively covered, the essays in this collection donotespeciallyaddressKant’sviewsonspatiotemporality,importantthoughthis topic is for grasping Kant’s idealism. An important goal of this volume is to fill a gapintheexistingliteratureregardingtheneedforanexplanationofanelementthat isequallyimportantforunderstandingKant’sdoctrineofidealism,namelyhispar- ticular view on logic and the discursivity of human judgment. Nevertheless, given theclosenessofthedoctrineofspatiotemporalityandKant’sviewofhumandiscur- sivitysomeoftheargumentspresentedintheessaysheredotouchuponaspectsthat concernspatiotemporality. The essays in the second part of this volume examine various lines of interpre- tationthatreflectspecificallyontherelationbetweenKant’stheoryofknowledge, in particular his transcendental logic underpinning it, and his idealism. One such lineofinquirywouldbetoexplore,inawaydifferentfromasimilartackbyHenry Allison,thepossibilityofshowingthatKant’sconceptionofdiscursivityitselfleads to transcendental idealism. This line is adopted, in various ways, in the essays by GaryBanham,SteveBayne,MarcelQuarfoodandDennisSchulting. In his article, Banham connects Kant’s idealist position to his Copernican Turn regardingthewayinwhichtheverynotionof‘object’isaproductoftheself-activity ofthesubjectandsoisdirectlyrelatedtohisdefinitionofthetranscendentalunity of apperception. The sense of objectivity that we have when we refer to physical objectsthereforerestsonsomebasicreferencetocombinatoryactivitybythesub- ject,whichconstituteswhatBanhamcallsthe‘idealismofapperception’.According toBayne,thereisawayofseeinganimportantandcloseconnectionbetweenKant’s transcendentalidealismandhistheoryofconcepts.Byfirstdistinguishingthecon- cepts as marks theory, the concepts as images theory, and the concepts as rules theory—whichhediscussesagainstthebackdropofLeibniz’,Locke’sandHume’s respective theories—Bayne subsequently points out that only the latter theory of viii Preface concepts as rules is necessary, though not sufficient, for establishing a transcen- dentalidealismbasedonKant’sCopernicanhypothesis,namelythehypothesisthat objectsmustconformtoa“rule”which,asKantassertsinafamouspassageinthe B-preface,“Ihavetopresupposeinmyselfbeforeanyobjectisgiventome,hencea priori”(Bxvii).Quarfooddefendsthethesisthatitisonlybywayofexaminingmore closely the contrast between human discursive understanding and non-discursive types of understanding that some peculiarities of Kant’s conception of idealism become more understandable, in particular his otherwise rather enigmatic state- ments about the relation between whole and parts in things in themselves. Finally inthispart,Schultingarguesthatidealismfollowsalreadyfromtheconstraintsthat the use of the categories, in particular the categories of quality, places on the con- ceivabilityofthingsinthemselves.Hisclaimisthat,althoughitisnotonlypossible but also necessary to think things in themselves, it doesn’t follow that by merely thinkingwehaveafullgraspofthenatureofthingsinthemselves. The separability issue not only concerns epistemological readings. Some have offered metaphysical interpretations that accommodate Kant’s talk about things in themselves and appearances whilst ignoring idealism, most prominently Rae LangtoninherbookKantianHumility(1998).Langtonhasherselfbeentheobject ofintensescrutiny.Intheintroductoryessaybelow,Schultingdiscussesinparticular Ameriks’critiqueofLangton’smetaphysicalpositiononKant’stranscendentaldis- tinction,whichatthesametimebringsintoviewhisowndistinctivemetaphysical readingofidealism.LucyAllais,whoinsomerespectsisclosetoLangton,takesa novelapproachtotheusualexclusionaryoptionsofbeingatwo-aspecteroratwo- worlder regarding the transcendental distinction.Inrecent work,shehas proposed thatthebestwaytoreadKant’sidealismisbyseeingitasatheorycommittedtothe reality of things that can be characterized in two ways, which correspond to their having an inner nature that is inaccessible to human minds and to their having an appearancenature,whichcanbecognizedbyus.It’sinthislastsense,intheman- nerthattheyaremind-dependent,thatthingsaremetaphysicallyideal,accordingto Allais.Intheintroductoryessay,SchultingelaboratesonAllais’views.Inherown articleinthisvolume,Allaislinkshermiddleroadapproachtotranscendentalide- alismtothequestionofseparabilityinthecontextoftheTranscendentalDeduction. Shethinksthattherearegoodreasonstobelievethatatleastonelineofthoughtin the Deduction may be compatible with straightforward realism. Allais thus argues that Kant’s argument for the possibility of objective experience is separable from hisargumentforidealism. Notwithstanding the great variety of interpretations of Kantian idealism, the majorityofcontemporaryreadingsstillappearstobebasedupontheassumptionthat the thing-in-itself is a self-standing numerically identical individual or entity that, as extramentally existing real thing, must in some sense correlate with the object asappearance.Agenuinelyneglectedalternativewouldbetoconsiderthething-in- itself,notasaself-standingentity,butasanecessarypostulatedobjectofReason, anensrationis,whichissuesfromtheconstraintsofthoughtitself,butwhichmust atthesametimestillbeaccountedforintermsofanuncognizable‘transcendental substratum’, as Kant calls it, or a reality underlying appearances, albeit that Kant appearstoseethenatureofthisrealityasdefinitelynon-empirical. Preface ix In the third part of the volume Dietmar Heidemann, Christian Onof, and Jacco Verburgt,eachintheirownwayandfromdifferentangles,consideraspectslinked totheissuesinvolvingthenatureor,indeed,theveryconceptofthething-in-itself orthe‘in-itself’,asOnofcallsit.HeidemannconsidersthequestionwhetherKant’s viewofthething-in-itselfcommitshimtoskepticism.Heidemannarguesthattran- scendental idealism is not a skeptical theory concerning the existence of things in themselves, since the distinction between appearances and things in themselves mustnotbeseenintermsoftraditionalskepticismwithrespecttotheexternalworld. TraditionalskepticismratherpresupposeswhatKanttermstranscendentalrealism, which holds that external objects exist in a strong ontological sense as things in themselvesindependentlyofourminds.Theunderlyingassumptionsoftheskepti- calhypothesis arethusnotcompatiblewithtranscendental idealism.Onoffocuses ontheissuehowwemustunderstandwhatitisforsomethingtohavean‘in-itself’ character on the basis of an explanation of the way we are causally affected by a thing. The ‘in-itself’, Onof argues, is the ground of affection and also that of which the empirical object is the appearance. Whilst we must think the ‘in-itself’ as conceptually indeterminate, its indeterminacy is a surplus of content character- izing its intrinsic nature. Onof’s proposed understanding of the ‘in-itself’ suggests it does not define an ontological realm distinct from that of empirical objects, but also that a dual-aspect interpretation of transcendental idealism is untenable. And finally,VerburgtstressestheneedforincludingtheTranscendentalDialecticofthe CritiqueofPureReasonintothediscussionaboutKant’sidealism.Verburgtconcen- trates on the section on the Transcendental Ideal in which Kant defines the notion of ‘the thing-in-itself’ in terms of an ideal of reason. He discusses in some detail Béatrice Longuenesse’s reading of this section and queries her more general view on the relation between the Analytic and the Dialectic, which reflects an inade- quateperspectiveonKant’sTranscendentalLogicandaconspicuousneglectofhis idealism. The contributors to this collection of essays do not agree with one another on everyaspectofKantianidealism.Whattheydo,however,agreeuponisthecontin- uingrelevanceofaddressingthetopicofidealism,notleastbecauseKant’soverall philosophy is often seen, rightly or wrongly, in the light of this controversial doc- trine. We believe that the essays collected here offer a comprehensive analysis of cardinal aspects of Kant’s idealism, which have hitherto not or insufficiently been consideredintheKantliterature. WewishtoacknowledgethesupportofASCA,inparticularEloeKingma,and theDepartmentofPhilosophyoftheUniversityofAmsterdamformakingthecon- ference Kant’s Transcendental Logic & Idealism, the proceedings of which lie at thebasisofpartofthisvolume,financiallypossible.Wewouldliketoexpressour gratitudetotheauthorswhocontributedtheirpapers.Wealsothankananonymous readerforSpringerforhishelpfulcommentsonthemanuscript,andnotleastIngrid vanLaarhovenforheroutstandingworkasoureditoratSpringer. London,England DennisSchulting Amsterdam,TheNetherlands JaccoVerburgt

Description:
This key collection of essays sheds new light on long-debated controversies surrounding Kant’s doctrine of idealism and is the first book in the English language that is exclusively dedicated to the subject. Well-known Kantians Karl Ameriks and Manfred Baum present their considered views on this m
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.