Yale Law School Yale Law School Legal Scholarship Repository Faculty Scholarship Series Yale Law School Faculty Scholarship 1996 Attainder and Amendment 2: Romer's Rightness Akhil Reed Amar Yale Law School Follow this and additional works at:https://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/fss_papers Part of theLaw Commons Recommended Citation Amar, Akhil Reed, "Attainder and Amendment 2: Romer's Rightness" (1996).Faculty Scholarship Series. 936. https://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/fss_papers/936 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Yale Law School Faculty Scholarship at Yale Law School Legal Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship Series by an authorized administrator of Yale Law School Legal Scholarship Repository. For more information, please [email protected]. ATTAINDERA ND AMENDMENT2 : ROMER'S RIGHTNESS Akhil Reed Amar* [T]he principle underlying the Court's opinion is that one who is ac- corded equal treatmentu nder the laws, but cannot as readily as others obtain preferential treatmentu nder the laws, has been denied equal pro- tection of the laws. If merely stating this alleged "equal protection" vio- lation does not suffice to refute it, our constitutionalj urisprudenceh as achieved terminals illiness. - Justice Antonin Scalia, dissenting in Romer v. Evans' Call me silly. In fact, call me terminally silly. For despite Justice Scalia's remarkably confident claim, I believe, and shall try to prove be- low, that the Romer Court majority opinion invalidating Colorado's Amendment 2 was right both in form and in substance, both logically and sociologically. I stress "form" and "logic" at the outset because I share Justice Scalia's belief in the importance of these things in consti- tutional adjudication. I also share his commitment to constitutional text, history, and structure, and his suspicion of "free-form" constitutional- ism.2 And so I shall highlight the text, history, and spirit of a constitu- tional clause that - though not explicitly invoked by the Romer major- ity - clarifies and supports the majority's theory: the Article I, section 10 Attainder Clause.3 My claim is not that the Equal Protection Clause, relied upon by the Romer Court, was incapable of doing the work; but that the sociology and principles underlying the Attainder Clause * SouthmaydP rofessorY, ale Law School.B .A. 1980, J.D. 1984, Yale.- Ed. I thankB ruce AckermanV, ik Amar, Jack Balkin, Guido CalabresiS, teve Calabresi, OwenF iss, Joe GoldsteinL, eslie HakalaE, rezK alir,N eal KatyalR, en6eL ettow,S andy Levinson,B urkeM arshallL, arryT ribe,E van Wolfson,a nd Kenji Yoshinof or their helpfulc omments. 1. 116 S. Ct. 1620, 1630 (1996) (Scalia,J ., dissenting). 2. Cf LaurenceH . Tribe, TakingT exta nd StructureS eriously:R eflections on Free- Form Method in ConstitutionalI nterpretation,1 08 HARV.L . REV. 1221 (1995). In this articleP rofessorT ribes uggestst hati n some of my work,I haves uccumbedto a "free- formm ethod"o f constitutionainl terpretatioInd. . at 1225 n.9, 1240, 1246-48,1 289-92. I pleadn ot guilty. 3. "No State shall ... pass any Bill of Attainder. . ." U.S. CONST.a rt. I, ? 10, cl. 1. A similar provision binds the federal government.S ee U.S. CONST.a rt. I, ? 9, cl. 3. 203 204 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 95:203 powerfully illuminate the facts of Romer, the opinions in Romer, and the spirit of the Equal ProtectionC lause itself.4 I. In Romer, the United States Supreme Court struck down the fol- lowing words - which had been adopted by a 1992 statewide referen- dum as an amendmentt o the Colorado Constitution- as unconstitu- tional on their face: No ProtectedS tatusB asedo n HomosexualL, esbiano, r BisexualO rienta- tion.N eithert he Stateo f Coloradot,h rougha ny of its brancheso r depart- ments,n or any of its agencies,p oliticals ubdivisionsm, unicipalitieos r schoold istrictss, halle nact,a dopto r enforcea ny statuter, egulationo, rdi- nance or policy wherebyh omosexuall, esbian or bisexual orientation, conductp, racticeso r relationshipssh allc onstituteo r otherwiseb e the ba- sis of or entitlea ny persono r class of personst o have or claim any mi- noritys tatus,q uotap referencesp, rotecteds tatuso r claim of discrimina- tion. This Section of the Constitutions hall be in all respects self- executing.5 Justice Kennedy wrote for a six-Justice majority.J ustice Scalia (joined by Chief Justice Rehnquist and Justice Thomas) let fly a stinging dissent. Since Romer came down, I have had many conversations about it with law professors and law studentsa cross the country.T he initial con- sensus seems to be that while Justice Kennedy's language soared, Jus- tice Scalia's logic held. Justice Kennedy won their hearts; Justice Scalia, their heads. I must confess that before I read Justice Kennedy's opinion which builds in part on an evocative amicus brief submitted by Laurence Tribe, John Hart Ely, Gerald Gunther, Philip Kurland, and Kathleen Sullivan6- I too had great difficulty in seeing how the Colo- rado referendumw as unconstitutional.I reasoned as follows: It is hard to see how, under existing equal protection doctrine, a simple declarationt hat "sexual orientationi s not just like race" is un- constitutional.T o be sure, a strong argumentc an be made that sexual orientation discrimination is like - indeed is itself a form of - sex 4. For a superb analysis of Romer that complements the one I shall offer here, see generally Daniel Farber & Suzanna Sherry, The Pariah Principle, 13 CONST.C OM- MENTARY (forthcoming 1996). 5. 116 S. Ct. at 1623 (quoting COLO.C ONST.a rt. II, ? 30b). 6. Brief of Laurence H. Tribe, John Hart Ely, Gerald Gunther,P hilip B. Kurland, and Kathleen M. Sullivan as Amici Curiae in Supporto f Respondents,R omer v. Evans, 116 S. Ct. 1620 (1996) (No. 94-1039) [hereinafterB rief]. Especially importanta nalysis appearsi d. at 6 n.2. October 1996] Romer's Rightness 205 discriminationB.7u t the SupremeC ourth as yet to see this light;a nd in any event, it has long treateds ex discriminatiodni fferentlyf rom race discriminationIn. doctrinajl argon,r ace discriminatiorne quires" strict scrutiny"w hile sex discriminationge nerates" intermediatsec rutiny."8 And so if the declaration" sex and sexualo rientationd iscriminatioanr e differentf rom race discrimination"is unconstitutionauln derS upreme Courte qualp rotectiond octrine,t hen the Constitutionit self - as con- struedb y the SupremeC ourt- is unconstitutionaAl. nd that idea is silly. Terminally. Thus, if Colorado'sc ities had never adoptedo rdinancesr equiring courts,i n effect, to give stricts crutinyt o sexualo rientationd iscrimina- tion, thatf ailuret o treats exualo rientatione xactlyl ike race would not have been unconstitutionauln derS upremeC ourte qualp rotectiond oc- 7. True, a ban on, say, gay marriagei s applied against both sexes - gay men and lesbian women. But a ban on interracialm arriagei s likewise applied against both blacks and whites. A ban on interracialm arriager equires formal race labeling: if the bride is white, the groom may many if white, but not if black. And so the government must have Nuremberg-likeb lood codes to determinei f the "octoroon" Homer Plessy is white or black. Similarly, a ban on gay marriager equires formal sex labeling: if the "bride" is a woman, the "groom" may marryi f a man, but not if a woman. And here too, "oc- toroon"-like problems emerge. What if the groom is a cross-dressingt ranssexual?O r has had (or is planning to have) a sex-change operation? Or is XXY? What if the "bride" is genetically male, but was born with female genitals (as sometimes happens naturally)?S o, just as miscegenation laws were not race-blind, sexual orientationl aws are not sex-blind. And moving beyond form to substance, the social meaning of misce- genation laws was the legal enactmento f racial hierarchy- trying to create the social and biological illusion of separate races (which cannot interbreed)r athert han a single human race (which can intrabreed):r eal whites stick with their own kind. So too, the social meaning of sexual orientationd iscriminationi s the legal enactment of chauvin- ism: real men sleep with real women. Heterosexism is a form of sexism that perpetuates traditionalg ender roles and chauvinism just as miscegenation laws were a form of ra- cism that perpetuatedt raditionalr ace roles and white supremacy. These ideas are developed in more detail in Andrew Koppelman,N ote, The Misce- genation Analogy: Sodomy Laws as Sex Discrimination, 98 YALEL .J. 145 (1988) and Andrew Koppelman,W hy Discrimination Against Lesbians and Gay Men Is Sex Dis- crimination, 69 N.Y.U. L. REV. 197 (1994). See also Sylvia Law, Homosexualitya nd the Social Meaning of Gender, 1988 Wis. L. REV. 187. 8. The Court, however, has recently left the door open to the argumentt hat sex discriminations hould perhaps receive strict scrutiny. See, e.g., J.E.B. v. Alabama, 114 S. Ct. 1419, 1425 n.6 (1994). But even if both kinds of discriminationg et strict scru- tiny, it is hard - at least right now - to think that, say, sex-segregated bathrooms would stand or fall with race-segregatedb athrooms. After its decision in Romer, the Supreme Court seemed to give even more "bite" to intermediates crutiny in the V.M.I. case, United States v. Virginia, 116 S. Ct. 2264 (1996), but even this case did not treat sex just like race. The Court did not, for exam- ple, categoricallyb an all single-sex state education on the theory that separate is inher- ently unequal. 206 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 95:203 trine.9 But surely if Denver, Aspen, and Boulder do enact ordinances treating sexual orientation like race for antidiscriminationp urposes, these cities are not forever barredf rom later repealing these ordinances. Repeal here is a kind of state action, but not an unconstitutionalk ind. The Constitution does not require that "special" antidiscrimination rights, once extended, irrevocably vest via some magic and an- tidemocratico ne-way ratchet. And if Denver, Aspen, and Boulder can repeal these ordinances,p resumablyt he Colorado legislature can repeal them by statute;a nd so too the people of Colorado can repeal them by state constitutionala mendment( via initiative or referendum).T o think otherwise is terminally silly.10 To be sure, Colorado's Amendment 2 "entrenches" its No Strict Scrutiny For Sexual OrientationD iscriminationR ule in the sense that opponents of the stingy rule can now prevail only by passing a new constitutionala mendmentr athert han a local ordinance or a state stat- ute. Passing a new constitutional amendment is of course an onerous task. But all constitutionalp rovisions entrench in this sense. The Strict Scrutiny For Race DiscriminationR ule in the FourteenthA mendment, as construed by the Supreme Court, itself entrenches in just this way. Opponents of this federal rule can now prevail only by passing a new federal constitutional amendment (rather than a state law or congres- sional statute).A nd, of course, it is notoriouslyt ough to pass a new fed- eral constitutional amendment.B ut surely that entrenchmentd oes not make the Fourteenth Amendment itself unconstitutional. To think it does would be terminally silly. The Denver, Aspen, and Boulder ordinances repealed by Amend- ment 2, however, did more than prohibit governmentf rom discriminat- ing on the basis of orientation.T he ordinances also prohibited certain forms of private discrimination- in employment and in housing, for example. But surely the cities were not constitutionallyo bliged to pass these private discriminationc odes. The federal Constitution generally does not require that the governmentp rohibit private discrimination.I f it did, the "state action" requiremento f the Equal ProtectionC lause - which bans governmentd iscriminationb ut not private discrimination 9. Imagine, for example, a city college affirmative action plan for gays. A race- based affirmativea ction policy would requires trict scrutiny;b ut must sexual orientation be treatedj ust like race here under Court precedents? 10. But cf. Washingtonv . Seattle Sch. Dist. No. 1, 458 U.S. 457 (1982); Hunterv . Erickson, 393 U.S. 385 (1969); Reitman v. Mulkey, 387 U.S. 369 (1967). On purely formal grounds,t hese cases are hard to understand.P erhapst he best way to make sense of them is that they frown on the entrenchmento f racial segregation and on excessive racial polarizationo f populist politics; and they reflect suspicion of "gerrymandered" proceduralr ules treatingr acial issues differentlyf rom other political issues. October 1996] Romer's Rightness 207 would itself be unconstitutional.A nd that idea would be - well, you get the point. For the reasons we have already seen, repeal is no differ- ent from failure to enact; and neither is repeal by dint of an "en- trenching" constitutionala mendment. II. How did Justice Kennedy's majority opinion deal with all this? Largely by side-stepping it through a more careful reading of Amend- ment 2, in a formal and textual analysis that should have commanded the respect, if not the assent, of a principledf ormalist/textualistli ke Jus- tice Scalia. Beyond this formal and textual analysis - which paid the Colorado electoratet he high compliment of taking their words seriously - Justice Kennedy's opinion showed remarkable sensitivity to the mean purpose and dark social meaning lurking beneath these words. Amendment2 , Justice Kennedy argued,d id not merely declare that sexual orientationi s not like race. Strictly speaking, it did not address sexual orientationp er se. Rather, it explicitly singled out for disfavored treatment "homosexual, lesbian [and] bisexual orientation."T wice the Amendment used these words, once in its caption. Under Amendment 2, heterosexuals could win local ordinances and state laws protecting themselves from being discriminateda gainst on the basis of their sexual orientation, but nonheteros could not win symmetric ordinances and laws. This point is not purely theoreticalb ut palpably real. Amendment 2 did not repeal Denver's, Aspen's, and Boulder's ordinances in toto, but only insofar as these ordinances protected homosexuals, lesbians, and bisexuals from orientationd iscrimination.U nder the Boulder Code (as modified by Amendment2 ), Boulder was not permittedt o discrimi- nate against heteros on the basis of their orientation,b ut homos and bis were shut out of this Code's sympatheticp rotection. Under Denver law (as modified by Amendment 2), a gay apartmentc omplex owner was barredf rom posting a "For Rent - No Straights" sign; but a straight apartmentc omplex owner was free to post a "For Rent - No Queers" sign. Thus, if a plaintiff filed a complaint that defendant fired her be- cause of her sexual orientation,a judge following both state and local law would have been obliged to ask her to amend her complaintb y stat- ing her orientation;a nd if she answered "gay," the judge would have been obliged to rule against her on this ground alone. Beneath this formal inequality - this exclusion from the law's protections because of who gays are - lurked substantive inequality, Kennedy argued. The Amendment itself, in its social meaning, was a kind of "No Queers" sign writ large. Its caption, "No ProtectedS tatus Based on Homosexual, Lesbian, or Bisexual Orientation," came un- 208 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 95:203 comfortablcyl ose to "No Protect[ionfo r] Homosexual[s]L, esbian[s]o r Bisexual[s]."I t was a kind of legal and social outlawryi n cowboy country- a targetingo f outsidersa, badgeo f second-classc itizenship, a taintingo f queers,a scarletQ . The queer( puni ntended)la nguageo f Amendmen2t - its odd and obsessives inglingo ut of all nonstandard sexualo rientation-s was a subtlec ue, a Freudians lip that old fash- ioned animusw as afoot here.11W hen a personb lurtso ut the n-word, we wonder;w hen a voting district looks utterlyu ncouthi n shape, judgesa re suspicious;1a2n d eyebrowsa re raisedw hen Coloradov oters adopta n amendmentth ati s "unprecedenteidn ourj urisprudence."'3 III. Thoughi t went unnamedin JusticeK ennedy'so pinion,t he Attain- der Clauseo f ArticleI , Section1 0 helpsc larifya ndi lluminateh is argu- ment and, as we shall see, offers lawyersl itigatingg ay rightsc ases a particularlryi ch and apt sourceo f doctrine.P erhapst he Courto mitted explicit mention of this Clause - and hinted at it only en passant - becausei t was not explicitlyi nvokedb y the parties( or by any of the many amici).'4B ut the SupremeC ourtm ay generallya ffirma correct dispositionb elow on any ground. (Indeed,a s we shall see, Justice Kennedy's opinion explicitly side-steppedt he Colorado Supreme Court'sb asis for invalidatingA mendmen2t , and thus affirmedo n an entirelyd ifferentt heoryt hant he courtb elow.)M orei mportantt,h e At- tainderC lause,i n its logic and spirit,i s an earlyf orebearo f the Equal ProtectionC lause,o n which the Courtd id lean. It is no surpriset, hen, that plaintiffs in the landmarkB olling v. Sharpe5'c ase - which held that federala ctionsw ere subjectt o equal protectionp rinciples- ex- plicitly relied on the AttainderC lause of ArticleI , Section 9, which speakss pecificallyt o federala ction.'6J im Crowl aws, plaintiffsa rgued, 11. Cf. Bowers v. Hardwick,4 78 U.S. 186, 200 (1986) (Blackmun, J., dissenting) (criticizing "the Court's almost obsessive focus on homosexual activity" in light of the fact that the Georgia statute at issue nowhere distinguished between homosexual and heterosexuals odomy). 12. See Gomillion v. Lightfoot, 364 U.S. 339 (1960); Shaw v. Reno, 509 U.S. 630 (1993). 13. Romer v. Evans, 116 S. Ct. 1620, 1628 (1996). 14. The brief submittedb y Professor Tribe and others, however, did explicitly in- voke the related idea of outlawry, and it pointedly cited pages from a Supreme Court case discussing outlawry and attainder.S ee Brief, supra note 6, at 10-11 (citing Com- munist Party v. Subversive Activities Control Bd., 367 U.S. 1, 82, 88 (1961)). 15. 347 U.S. 497 (1954). 16. See RICHARDK LUGER, SIMPLEJ USTICE5 22 (1994) (discussing the causes of action pled in the Bolling complaint). October 1996] Romer's Rightness 209 had the purposea nd effect of stigmatizingb lacks- not for whatt hey did, but for who they were. And that,p laintiffsa rgued,w as a kind of attaindera, legislativelyi mposeds taina nd taint.17 To see this morec learly,a ndt o see the implicationfso r Romer,l et us proceedt hrougha serieso f hypotheticals. HypotheticaOl ne. "The Anti-AmarL aw. Akhil Reed Amars hall be drawn,h anged,a nd quarteredH. is privatep artss hall be cut off, his blood shall be deemedc orrupteda, nd his childrens hall be strippedo f their inheritancefr om him." This is a textbooka ttainderh, istorically speaking.'8A courtm ay imposea deaths entenceo n a namedi ndivid- ual, but a legislature may not. And so this law is obviously unconstitutional. In part,t he nonattainderru le is rootedi n narrowi deas of adjudica- tive due process.B eforea personi s madet o suffera criminals anction, he musth ave his day in court,w ith individuanl otice of the charges,a n opportunityto be heardi n his own defense,t he assistanceo f counsel, the chancet o confronto pposingw itnessesi n a proceedingg overnedb y properr uleso f evidencea nd relevancea, nd so forth.1L9 egislatureos p- 17. For further elaboration of this theory, see Akhil Reed Amar, Constitutional Rights in a Federal System: RethinkingI ncorporation and Reverse Incorporation, in BENCHMARKSG: REAT CONSTITUTIONACLO NTROVERSIEISN THE SUPREME COURT7 1, 79-81 (TerryE astlande d., 1995). See also Tribe, supra note 2, at 1298-99 n.247 (similarly suggesting that the Bolling result could be defended on Attainder Clause grounds, thus avoiding the awkwardnesso f "reverse incorporation"). On the connection in Anglo-Americanl aw between attaindera nd notions of stain and taint, see 1 OXFORD ENGLISH DICTIONARY 761 (2d ed. 1989); infra note 41. 18. See United States v. Brown, 381 U.S. 437, 441 (1965); 3 JOSEPHS TORY, COMMENTARIEOSN THEC ONSTITUTIOONF THEU NITEDS TATES? 1338, at 209-10 (Boston, Hilliard, Gray & Co. 1833); LAURENCEH . TRIBE,A MERICANC ONSTITU- TIONALL AW ? 10-4, at 641-42 (2d ed. 1988). In beginning with the "paradigmc ase" under the AttainderC lause, I here follow the interpretivea pproacha dvocatedb y Profes- sor Rubenfeld. See Jed Rubenfeld,R eading the Constitutiona s Spoken, 104 YALEL .J. 1119, 1169-73 (1995). My Hypothetical,t hough graphic, accuratelyr epresentst he obvious fixation on the body and the private parts- the insides - of the real-life attainderv ictim. The typical, highly ritualizeds entence of one attaintedo f treason in England was as follows: You are to be drawn upon a hurdlet o the place of execution, and there you are to be hanged by the neck, and being alive cut down, and your privy-memberst o be cut off, and your bowels to be taken out of your belly and there burned, you be- ing alive; and your head to be cut off, and your body to be divided into four quarters,a nd that your head and quartersb e disposed of where his majesty shall think fit. J.H. Baker, Criminal Courts and Procedure at CommonL aw 1550-1800, in CRIMEI N ENGLAND1, 550-1800, at 15, 42 (J.S. Cockbur ed., 1977). 19. See United States v. Lovett, 328 U.S. 303, 316-18 (1946) (invalidatingo n At- tainder Clause grounds a congressional act that in effect condemned three named per- sons "without the safeguards of a judicial trial"); Cummings v. Missouri, 71 U.S. (4 Wall.) 277, 323 (1867) ("A bill of attainderi s a legislative act which inflicts punish- 210 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 95:203 erating in the ordinaryl egislative mode do not typically abide by these adjudicativep rocedures,a nd so trial and sentencing by legislatures are banned.20 But the nonattainderr ule goes much deeper, tapping into basic principles of separationo f powers and equal protection. Even if Con- gress were willing to give me a hearing before attaintingm e, the Con- stitutionb ars it from acting as a court (outside the strictly circumscribed impeachmentp rocess). In general, the legislature must prescribe penal- ties generally and prospectively,b ehind a suitably impersonalv eil of ig- norance: "All persons who do X in the future shall be hanged." Those who seek to avoid the noose are thus given fair warning that they must refrain from conduct X. Without the nonattainderp rinciple, the legisla- ture could simply single out its enemies - or the politically unpopular - and condemn them for who they are, or for what they have done in the past and can no longer change. Here we see an obvious link be- tween the nonattainderr ule and the related ban on ex post facto laws. Indeed, in both Article I, Section 9, limiting Congress, and Article I, Section 10, limiting states, the Attainder and Ex Post Facto Clauses stand side-by-side. A court independento f the legislaturem ay condemn a named person for what he has done in the past; courts operate retro- spectively and specifically in discrete cases and controversies: United States v. Amar. But a court must treat like cases alike and may apply only the general criminal norms previously laid down by statute or cus- tom, rathert han whatever criminal rules the judges might prefer were they legislators. By separatingt he process of penal lawmaking and pe- nal adjudication,t he Constitutionp rotects both liberty and equality and promotes the rule of law; the legislature can only prescribe new penal rules for all, and the judiciary can only apply pre-existing penal laws against named individuals.21B oth legislation and adjudicationm ust be suitably impersonal.N either legislators nor judges can punish me sim- ply because they do not like me. Suppose, however, that the legislature does not itself purportt o ad- judicate guilt and impose a criminal sentence as a court, but instead ment without a judicial trial .... [T]he legislative body . . . pronounces upon the guilt of the party, without any of the forms or safeguards of trial ...."); 3 STORY, supra note 18, at 210-11; TRIBE,s upra note 18, at 641, 657-63; Charles H. Wilson, Jr., Comment, The SupremeC ourt'sB ill of AttainderD octrine: A Need for Clarification,5 4 CAL. L. REV.2 12, 242-46 (1966). 20. On the applicability of the Attainder Clause to popular referenda, see infra note 59. 21. See generally United States v. Brown, 381 U.S. 437 (1965); Note, The Bounds of Legislative Specification:A Suggested Approach to the Bill of Attainder Clause, 72 YALE L.J. 330 (1962). October1 996] Romer's Rightness 211 passesa cleverv arianto f the Anti-AmaLr aw:" It shallh enceforth(p ro- spectively)b e a (general)c rimef or anyonet o be Akhil Reed Amar,t o have his blood type, feelings, fingerprintsa,n d DNA. The courtss hall applyt his (general)l aw and accorda ny defendantth e traditionapl roce- duralr ightso f notice, opportunityto be heard,c ounsel,c onfrontation, and so forth.A nyonef oundg uilty of this (general)c rimei n courts hall be drawn,h anged,q uarterede,t c." Obviouslyt, his too is a textbookb ill of attaindere ven though it purportst o leave "adjudication"o f the "crime"t o independenct ourts.I t is an attainderb ecause,d espite its dishonestp rotestationsit, fails the requisitet est of generalitya nd pros- pectivityI. t makesi t a capitalc rimet o be who I am.22P ut anotherw ay, it wrongly designates criminals rathert han crimes.23 HypotheticalT wo. "The Anti-Amara nd Public Stigma Law. Akhil Reed Amars hall be placedi n the publics tocksf or two hours.H is pri- vate parts shall be painted red.24P assersby may mock, insult, and hu- miliate him." In England, this was known as a "bill of pains and penal- ties" because it prescribed lesser punishment than that prescribed in 22. Thomas Wentworth,t he Earl of Strafforda nd one of the most famous attainder victims ever, was beheadedi n 1641, simply for being himself. For a grippinga ccount of this iniquity, see ZECHARIAHC HAFEEJ, R., THREEH UMANR IGHTSI N THEC ONSTI- TUTIONO F 1787, at 109-13 (1956). 23. My claim here is not that every attainderm ust be a law that makes it a crime to be who I am, but that every such law must be an attainder.L ater, I shall generalize the principle by suggesting that - whatever else it might also ban - the Attainder Clause frowns on all penal laws based on status or identity. The AttainderC lause implicates at least five basic constitutionali deals, not all of which are present in every attainderc ase. First, as we have seen, the Clause implicates rights of individualizeda djudicatoryp rocess - due process rights of notice and the op- portunityt o be heard. Second, the Clause affirms separationo f powers and rule of law notions of generality, prospectivity, transparency,a nd impersonality.T hird, the Clause anticipatest he equal protectioni dea banning stigmatic penalties imposed on an unpopu- lar person or group based on status, especially when laws reflect revulsion toward im- pure, corrupt,o r degraded bodies or body parts. Fourth, the Clause, when read in light of its history, calls for special sensitivity and judicial skepticism when a legislature sin- gles out political agitators or opposition speakers for disfavored treatment.S ee Brown, 381 U.S. at 441, 453 (invalidating,o n AttainderC lause grounds, a congressional act pe- nalizing the CommunistP arty by name, and noting that "political group[s] ... were the targets of the overwhelming majority of English and early American bills of attain- der"); David Kairys, Note, The Bill of AttainderC lauses and Legislative and Adminis- trative Suppressiono f "Subversives,"6 7 COLUML. . REV. 1490, 1499 (1967); Wilson, supra note 19, at 235-37. Finally, the Clause reflects a libertarians cheme of checks and balances by preventing any single branch of government from unilaterally depriving persons of life, liberty, or property.S ee Akhil Reed Amar, The Bill of Rights as a Con- stitution, 100 YALEL .J. 1131, 1194 (1991). In the Hypotheticalst hat follow, I shall es- pecially pursue the second, third, and fourth strandsn oted above. For a superb general treatmento f the AttainderC lause from which I have greatly profited, see TRIBE,s upra note 18, ?? 10-4 to -6. 24. See supra note 18.
Description: