Aristotle Dictionary Thomas P. Kiernan PHILOSOPHICAL LIBRARY New York Table of Contents Title Page Foreword ARISTOTLE - Introduction KEY OF REFERENCES A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W Y Z BIBLIOGRAPHY Foreword Aristotle was born at Stagira in Thrace, in the year 384 B.C., son of Nicomachus, a Doctor and personal physician of the King of Macedonia, Amyntas II. At the age of seventeen Aristotle was sent to Athens in continuance of his studies. The profession of medicine had been in his family for many generations, and perhaps because he was brought up in an atmosphere that was closely related to medicine and to the theories of the healing art, such a background could explain his gift, later to be manifested across broad areas of knowledge, for the concrete and the positive, for experiment and analysis. Upon his arrival in Athens, he became a member of Plato’s Academy, and for twenty years he was in the discipleship of Plato until the latter’s death in 348-7 B.C. While at the Academy, Aristotle found in Plato a friend and teacher for whom he had the greatest reverence, and although Aristotle’s eventual teachings were to be to a large degree grounded on disagreements with Platonic theory, he was, during his apprenticeship, a devoted student of his master. After Plato’s death, Aristotle left the Academy with Xenocrates and journeyed to Assos, where, under the sponsorship of Hermias, ruler of Atarneus, he established a Platonic community in which he put forth the beginnings of his own autonomous teachings. Three years later, after having married Pythias, the daughter of Hermias, he went to Mitylene on the island of Lesbos, where he met Theophrastus, who was to become his most ardent and celebrated disciple. By this time he had acquired a modest reputation throughout Greece, and in 342 he was summoned to Pella by King Philip of Macedonia in order to take the principal hand in the education of the King’s son, Alexander, who was then thirteen years old, and who was subsequently to play so great a role on the political stage of the era as Alexander the Great. When Alexander assumed the reins of the kingdom in 336-5, Aristotle left Macedonia for Athens, by way of Stagira, his birthplace, which had been rebuilt by Alexander in compensation for Aristotle’s pedagogical services. Returning to Athens in 335-4, Aristotle founded his own school, the Lyceum. For ten years he lived and worked there, presenting the great body of his system in the form of lectures. In 323, following the death of Alexander the Great, there was in Greece a great reaction against the Macedonian suzerainty, and Aristotle found himself in peril because of his association with Alexander and because the Lyceum was established under Macedonian protection. He therefore fled to Chalcis, the birthplace of his mother, where he lived for a year before his death in 322-1. The circumstances surrounding Aristotle’s writings are lodged in a curious paradox. The writings which he designated for general publication—the esoteric works—and which were well known in antiquity, are now for the most part lost and unknown, whereas those which were written for presentation to his students and colleagues—the pedagogical works—and which were relatively obscure in antiquity, are those which have survived. These latter works are, of course, extremely complicated and axiomatic in style due to the fact that they were intended for limited and highly specialized scholarly consumption. On the other hand, those works written for public consumption were of a much more graceful literary style, fluidly oratorical and discursive, and in quite stark contrast to the prosaic severity of his scholastic writings. There remain of his public works only fragments, the most numerous of which belong to the dialogues Protrepticus and Eudemus. These fragments come out of his earliest writing period, when he was still under the direct influence of Plato. It is evident that in this earliest period— it is generally agreed that his work falls into three main periods—he held without much reservation to the Platonic philosophy. In his second period Aristotle began to separate himself from Platonic theory, becoming less the poetic philosophizer and more the empirical scientist. He criticized Plato’s theory of Forms or Ideas, and took profound issue with the formerly held distinction between matter and form, negating the contention that these two terms constitute a dualism. He maintained, on the other hand, that matter and form are indissolubly united to form what is truly real being. Aristotle’s third period was that of his engagement in the Lyceum, where his genius for the organization of detailed research in the realms of nature and history awesomely manifested itself. The method and spirit of intensely incisive research into the phenomena of nature and history, which Aristotle fathered, represented something completely new in the Greek culture, and of course it still has its ramifications in the contemporary world. And yet there is no evidence from which to conclude that Aristotle, the growing empiricist, ever abandoned the more poetical flight through metaphysical speculation. The Aristotelian system, or Aristotelianism, is not a radical contradiction of Platonism, as has often been held. Rather it is, if not a continuance of Plato’s theories, at least an extension of Platonic thought. Historically speaking, Aristotelianism is the development of Platonism, through critical examination based on empirical evidence and physical fact, into a new metaphysics constructed on synthesis. Plato’s metaphysics was a subjective, one-sided flower of the imagination. Aristotle’s was a comprehensive and intricately landscaped garden of empirically supported logic. T.P.K. We cannot speak of injustice between master and slave, or between father and child or toward what is part of one’s self. Though we can speak of justice between a man and his wife it is not on the same level as between citizens not in the same immediate family. Between citizens justice is partly natural and partly conventional, the natural being valid everywhere and it does not depend on the individual’s acceptance or rejection. The conventional varies among individuals and is prescribed for a definite circumstance, such as measures of corn and wine. What is just and what is equitable are generically the same but the equitable is better. The reason is that every law is laid down in general terms and in accord with what holds for the majority of cases, whereas in concrete circumstances a particular case may be an exception and so the just must be amended. As amended we have the equitable in that particular case. An equitable man is willing to take less than his due even when the law is on his side. After this analysis of the moral virtues Aristotle proceeds to a study of the intellectual virtues since virtue implies a mean as prescribed by right reason according to some standard. What is right reason and what is its standard? To answer this we must remember that the soul involves both rational and irrational activities and that the rational part of the soul involves both a scientific or demonstrative power and a calculative or deliberative power. Moreover, the powers that guide us in action and the grasp of the truth are sense, reason and desire. Sense cannot originate action and, of the other two, reasoning has two modes, viz. affirmation and negation, and desire involves pursuit and avoidance. Since moral virtue is a formed power of choice and choice is desire following deliberation, the calculation or reasoning must be true and the desire right and this regards the practical rather than the speculative. So purpose is either desiring reason or reasoning desire about what is to be done or avoided. The mind arrives at truth by means of art, science, prudence, wisdom and understanding. Scientific knowledge is invariable and its object is necessary, eternal and invariable. Science can be taught. Induction is the process toward universal principles; syllogism (scientific reasoning) starts from these and proceeds to scientific conclusions. Hence, science is a formed habit of demonstration as explained in the Posterior Analytics. What is variable includes what man makes and what he does. The habit of making according to right reason is art, the habit of acting according to proper calculation is prudence. Prudence cannot be science because the sphere of prudence is action concerning what is variable; it cannot be art because it deals with doing rather than making. So prudence is a habit of calculative reason which issues in action in the domain of human good and evil. Wisdom is the union of intuitive reason with scientific knowledge concerning the noblest of objects and it is the same for all men, whereas prudence is relative to the matters of deliberation concerning the variable in matters of practice. Wisdom deals with the general, prudence with the particular facts, for it issues in action. Prudence may be called practical wisdom. Its types relate to the proper management of a household (oekonomia), the legislative faculty and statesmanship, either deliberative or judicial. Just as understanding (intuitive reason) deals with primary principles which cannot be demonstrated, prudence deals with particular facts which cannot be scientifically proved. What is this calculation or deliberation which prudence involves? It is not science or happy guessing or sagacity or just any kind of opinion but rather a correctness of reasoning (dianoia) by which we come to right conclusions in the correct manner and at the right time as to what ought to be done concerning the means to an end. It implies the exercise of intelligence, good judgment or discernment and correct reasoning. So intuitive reason is basic to both ultimate scientific truths and the principles of correct conduct. In virtue of our apprehension of the fundamentals of morality we deliberate about the proper means to our end. The conclusions of our deliberation are intuitively understood as the principles of conduct. We understand that the good is to be done, that such and such is good in such and such circumstances and therefore, we understand that it is to be done here and now. Prudence, as a virtue of the practical intellect, does not give us just a knowledge of the good but it produces the good act as ensuring the rightness of the means as moral virtue guarantees the rightness of the end. For, e.g. just acts involve both a knowledge that the acts are just and the performance of them by deliberate purpose for their own sake. “It is impossible to be prudent without being morally good,” and virtue is a habit implying right reason. So if Socrates held that moral virtues are forms of reason he was partly right, if he meant that they imply reason. He is wrong if he meant simply that all virtues are forms of prudence. And prudence does not rule wisdom but “rules in its interests.” There are three types of moral states to be avoided: vice, whose opposite is virtue, incontinence, the contrary of which is continence, and brutishness, whose opposite is god-likeness. Having discussed virtue and vice he will now consider incontinence and softness and their opposites which are not vices and virtues but dispositions of a different kind. The usual method of dialectical discussion of current opinions is carried out so that all error can be wiped out and truth left in possession of the agora. Continence and hardiness are considered good and praiseworthy; incontinence and softness are bad and blameworthy. This is quite evident but in what sense can a man judge rightly and act incontinently, as some contend taking incontinence to mean “uncontrolled by reason”? The self-
Description: