ebook img

ARISTOTLE AND ADORNO Caleb J. Basnett A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY ... PDF

604 Pages·2015·2.55 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview ARISTOTLE AND ADORNO Caleb J. Basnett A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY ...

POLITICS AND THE AESTHETIC ANIMAL: ARISTOTLE AND ADORNO Caleb J. Basnett A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF GRADUATE STUDIES IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY GRADUATE PROGRAM IN POLITICAL SCIENCE, YORK UNIVERSITY TORONTO, ONATRIO FEBRUARY, 2015 © Caleb J. Basnett, 2015 Abstract This study examines the neglected role of other animals and art in Aristotle’s classic conception of the human being, and argues that the work of T.W. Adorno can be drawn upon to recover this conception’s neglected promise. By reading Aristotle’s oft-cited claim that ‘the human being is by nature a political animal’ in light of his works on biology and poetics, I find that Aristotle displaces ideas concerning the role of human being in the cosmos prominent in the Ancient Greek world, binding the self-understanding of human beings to other animals and the arts. This self-understanding can be summarized as follows: 1) Aristotle recognizes that humans are not the only political animals, and provides the rudiments of a theory concerning how nonhuman politics might be possible; and 2) Aristotle’s theory of nature is unintelligible without artistic metaphors that suggest the creative power of the arts to produce what we understand to be human, not simply in terms of revealing natural human capacities, but in creating these capacities in the first place. Though largely unappreciated by his descendants, detractors, and even Aristotle himself, I argue these insights can be recovered through Adorno’s critical theory. Adorno enables us to grasp the creative power of art in the construction of the human being and the distance it can place between humans and other animals while at once allowing us to see how a turn toward the repressed possibilities upon which the emergence of the human depends is also a turn toward animality. In this sense, the promise of humanity and its legacy concerns less a defense of the classical humanism being eroded by the vicissitudes of history, than the possibility of uncovering the paths not followed by this tradition that might inform posthuman subjective possibilities more able to confront the challenges of the present. In this way, Adorno enables the theorization of an aesthetic animal, the subject of a radically transformed society. ii Acknowledgements During my time at York working on this project I have incurred numerous debts to professors, colleagues, and friends for their help and support, a few of which I would like to highlight here. Firstly, I would like to thank my committee, especially my supervisor Asher Horowitz, and readers Shannon Bell and Martin Breaugh, for their time and their helpful comments and criticisms. I also owe my thanks to the examiners, Stephen Newman, J.J. McMurtry, and Andrew Biro, both for their insightful comments, and for their willingness to take on this project in the first place. Secondly, I would like to thank past and present colleagues at York, Jordan Brennan, Cohen Brown, Elliott Buckland, Karl Dahlquist, Jason Harman, Paul Herbert, Christopher Holman, Arthur Imperial, Nadia Hasan, Rachel Magnusson, Paul Mazzocchi, James McMahon, Devin Penner, and Daniel Ross, for time spent arguing over coffee or beer, and their general camaraderie. York would not have been the experience it was had it not been for them. Lastly, I would like to thank my family: my partner Nagisa, and our children, Taiyo and Hazuki, for never jumping ship, even when icebergs loomed, and my friends Mike Blezy, Alex Buchinski, Max Capelliez, Ian Mackell, the Onishi family, and Sheela Subramanian, for tolerating me all these years. I ought also to note the unrepayable debt owed to my parents, Wendy and Richard, and my sisters, Caitlin and Cassandra, and their families. Try as one might, none of the aforementioned can be held responsible for the various inadequacies of this study, for which I take sole responsibility. iii Table of Contents Abstract………………………………………………………………………………………………………ii Acknowledgments……………………………………………………………………………………….iii Table of Contents…………………………………………………………………………………………iv Chapter One: Introduction…………………………………………………………………………….1 A Sketch in Triptych………………………………………………………………………….......1 Humans, Animals, and Art in Political Theory……………………………................8 A Forecast……………………………………………………………………………………………21 Part I: Art, Aesthetics, and the Human-Animal Divide.........................................26 Introduction………………………………………………………………………………………..26 Chapter Two: The Posteriority of the Human……………………………….……………….32 Rancière……………………………………………………………………………………………..32 Nancy………………………………………………………………………………………………….39 Agamben…………………………………………………………………………………………….42 The Posteriority of the Human………………………………………………………………45 Chapter Three: The Priority of Art: Heidegger and Nietzsche…………………………47 The Origin of the Work of Art………………………………………………………………..48 The Birth of Tragedy…………………………………………………………………………….58 The Will to Power…………………………………………………………………………………64 Chapter Four: Art, Aesthetics, and Animality: Between Heidegger and Nietzsche………………………………………………………….71 Foucault………………………………………………………………………………………………73 Agamben…………………………………………………………………………………………….78 Deleuze……………………………………………………………………………………………….83 Derrida……………………………………………………………………………………………….90 Conclusion: Back to Aristotle………………………………………………………………..98 Part II: Aristotle on Animality and the Human Being: The Biological Writings……………………………………………………………………….105 Introduction………………………………………………………………………………………106 Chapter Five: Humans and Animals in the World of Poetic Myth………………....115 From Homer to the Tragedians…………………………………………………………….115 Plato the Tragedian?......................................................................................128 iv Chapter Six: What is an Animal? Aristotle on Human Animality…………………..142 From the Soul to the Body…………………………………………………………………..143 Life Activity, Psychic Potential, and Politics…………………………………………..151 Chapter Seven: What is Humanity? The Human Excess………………………………169 Thought and the Intellectual Powers…………………………………………………….170 The Human Senses…………………………………………………………………………….180 The Human Body……………………………………………………………………………….183 Monsters……………………………………………………………………………………………191 Chapter Eight: Human Plurality and Inequality………………………………………….199 On Sexual Difference………………………………………………………………………….201 ‘Low Sorts’ and the Physical Features of the Best Human……………………….212 Conclusion: Knowledge, Sensation, Animality, and Art………………………….220 Part III: Art, Politics, and the Best Human Life in Aristotle………………………….227 Introduction………………………………………………………………………………………227 Chapter Nine: Natural Artifice and the Artifice of Nature………………………........237 The Artificial Body……………………………………………………………………………..238 Nature as Artist………………………………………………………...............................242 Chapter Ten: Art and the Most Choiceworthy Life………………..……………………..248 Beauty, Labor, and Leisure………………………………………………………………….249 Tragedy and the Best Life in the Poetics……………………………………………….262 Chapter Eleven: Tragedy and Contemplative Action…………………………………….275 Thought as Action: Tragic Speech………………………………………………………..277 Theory as Action: Tragic Spectatorship………………………………………………..286 Equity and Justice in Polity…………………………………………………………………303 Conclusion: From Aristotle to Adorno………………………………………………….316 Part IV: Enter Adorno, Stage Left……………………………………………......................331 Introduction: Adorno and Some Assorted Technical Problems Concerning Time-Travel……………………………………………………………………..331 Chapter Twelve: Jewgreek is greekjew: Aristotle, Hegel, and Adorno on the Perils of Dialectic…………………………..343 Adorno’s Aristotle………………………………………………………………………………343 Non-Identity and Dialectic………………………………………………………………….359 Constellation of Objects.................................................................................370 v Chapter Thirteen: Adorno on Humanism and the Human Being…………………..382 Humane Humanity…………………………………………………………………………….387 Reconciled Humanity…………………………………………………………………………394 The Question of Progress……………………………………………………………………400 Chapter Fourteen: Relatively Modest Horrors: Adorno and Animals……………..411 Anthropology, Dialectical and Otherwise……………………………………………..416 Animal Violence in Human Constitution………………………………………………431 Non-Identity as Human Animality……………………………………………………….447 The Utopian Animal…………………………………………………………………………..459 Chapter Fifteen: The Politics of an Aesthetic Animal……………………………………476 Mimesis…………………………………………………………………………………………….485 Morality and Politics…………………………………………………………………………..497 The Inhuman Addendum…………………………………………………………………….510 Inhuman Art………………………………………………………………………………………523 Animal Technique………………………………………………………………………………543 Chapter Sixteen: Conclusion………………………………………………………………………557 The Animality of Human Plurality and Other Suffering Animals…………….560 Future Avenues, Possibilities……………………………………………………………….569 Bibliography…………………………………………………………………………......................577 vi Chapter One: Introduction A Sketch in Triptych In The Time Machine (1895), H.G. Wells describes the feeling of time travel as “excessively unpleasant”: one is hurtled through time in a “helpless headlong motion” as if riding a “switchback,” gripped by a “nightmare sensation of falling” and “horrible anticipation” of “an imminent smash.”1 The world in which Wells’ time traveler finds himself proves worthy of these premonitory sensations, for it is a world wherein the working class, driven into a troglodytic existence, has returned to prey on its erstwhile oppressors. In Wells’ future the poor finally eat the rich, though history is ironic enough to avoid the rudeness of cannibalism— they have, in this distant future, become different species. While there is much that might be said of this tangle of ideas, what I wish to extract here is the idea that socio-political domination is bound up with nature, and that ‘time travel’ might reveal the transformations undergone by humans in relation to other animals—that the natural or even permanent appearance of humanity in any single image might, through the juxtaposition with others, reveal history through their frayed edges. With Wells, then, we might become time travelers in order to glimpse the three images of humanity, which, together, form the triptych that I claim intimates something of the transformation of the self- 1 H.G. Wells, The Time Machine, ed. Nicholas Ruddick (Peterborough: Broadview, 2001), 76-77. 1 understanding of human nature through history, and its relation to socio-political domination. If we have the stomach, then, we might leap: Venice, circa 1550. Tintoretto’s The Creation of Animals depicts part of the creation story found in the Book of Genesis. An anthropomorphic God is suspended above the earth, as if having leapt into the air: the upper-half of His body bent forward, His right hand extended. It is an active, theatrical pose— perhaps too much so, for a God who need only speak for it to be so. He is dressed in a blue robe and red cloak, and around His body is a kind of aura of light, delineating His separation and independence from the world of His creation, and which appears arranged around Him. There is a clear distinction between land, sky, and sea, and each is teeming: beasts of the field, birds of the air, fish of the sea. All appear to be moving at His behest, in straight lines even; they are ordered in a world and occupy a particular place in it according to their kind in the manner designated by their Creator, who stands apart from them. Beneath this image another stirs, as if the first were a kind of palimpsest, for Tintoretto based the composition of this piece upon a painting completed only some thirty years earlier in the same city: Titian’s Bacchus and Ariadne (c. 1523). Here it is Bacchus who is suspended in mid-air, having leapt from his chariot towards Ariadne, who is dressed in a blue robe and red cloak. In his wake is a procession of other figures, including animals, creatures half-human and half- animal, and others who at a glance could be either god or human. Unlike the 2 order built on the clear symmetry of the positioning of the animals and the prominence of their Creator in Tintoretto, Titian gives us here an image of disorder, of unruliness—not quite chaos, for Bacchus does appear to occupy a position of authority among his horde, but his position appears relative and unstable. Confronted with this procession, Ariadne’s fate is also unclear: will she be recruited by this mob, or even made its Lord? Or will they enslave her, or tear her apart and devour her, as they appear to have done a calf whose remains they parade around as trophies? The image, shorn of other knowledge of her story, does not say. In Tintoretto we see the dominant interpretation of the human-animal distinction as it is found in the Christian tradition. Though, strictly speaking, no human appears in the painting, insofar as “man” was made in the image of God and it is this special relation to God that sets him apart from other animals, we might see humans as occupying an analogical position to God in the painting, as creatures who, made in the image of God, share in His dominion over animals. Humans may, like animals, be in the world, but their relation to God means that they are not of the world: the realization of their properly human nature extends beyond the world of animals, and toward the eternal and divine. This division of human from animal through divine proximity strips the animal of the possibility of making moral claims. At best, the mistreatment of the animal can be seen as wrong due to what it does to the human agent involved: that the human either 3 violates divine law or fails to rise to its semi-divine stature when it mistreats others—these others do not matter in their own right. Yet this image draws upon another, very different image: the world of Greek mythology as it is captured by Titian. Here the line between human, animal, and god is far from clearly drawn, and we have no reason to believe it is stable. The remains of an animal are being bandied about—so it is not a world without violence—but other animals occupy different positions, and there is no indication that one is fundamentally different from another. That is, there is no evidence that a human could not occupy the position of an animal, or an animal, the position of a human, and the gods and other creatures appear to circulate between these two categories, occupying one and then the other as they desire. Thus the relation here between human and animal takes on different shapes particular to context: the animal might represent a foe to be subdued, or a potential friend whose allegiance must be secured through various rites; what matters is how the relation with the animal might secure or threaten one’s own status as human and so define the kind of human one is. Despite the apparent incongruity of these images, their historical and geographical proximity betrays their hidden unity. This image of an unruly separation between human and animal, where each appear to be continuous with the other in some important way, lies beneath the image of orderly separation according to the design of the Creator, and is never quite excised by the latter. 4

Description:
suspended above the earth, as if having leapt into the air: the upper-half of His . through it that Titian and the world of poetic myth appear as past, and . 7 See Alasdair MacIntyre, Dependent Rational Animals (Chicago: Open .. repeated today, though its sources appear to be as old as Pythagoras.
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.