ebook img

A Dialogue About Principle and a Principled Dialogue: Justice Iacobucci’s Substantive Approach to Dialogue PDF

30 Pages·0.308 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview A Dialogue About Principle and a Principled Dialogue: Justice Iacobucci’s Substantive Approach to Dialogue

A Dialogue About Principle and a Principled Dialogue: Justice Iacobucci’s Substantive Approach to Dialogue Roach, Kent. University of Toronto Law Journal, Volume 57, Number 2, Spring 2007, pp. 449-477 (Article) Published by University of Toronto Press For additional information about this article http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/tlj/summary/v057/57.2roach.html Access Provided by York University at 10/15/11 3:05PM GMT Kent Roach* A DIALOGUE ABOUT PRINCIPLE AND A PRINCIPLED DIALOGUE: JUSTICE IACOBUCCI’S SUBSTANTIVE APPROACH TO DIALOGUE I Introduction FrankIacobucciplayedtheleadroleinintroducingthemetaphorofjudi- cial review as a form of dialogue between courts and legislatures into Canadianconstitutionallaw.1Hediscusseddialogueinreferencetointer- pretingbothrightsandlimitationsundertheCanadianCharterofRights and Freedoms,2 but also in relation to devising remedies under the Charter3 and using the s. 33 override.4 Justice Iacobucci’s interest in dia- loguewasnot,however,limitedtothesemanydifferentaspectsofCharter adjudication. He recognized the importance of dialogue between courts andlegislatureswithrespecttothedevelopmentofthecommonlaw5and in the interpretation of statutes.6 One of the strengths of the dialogue metaphor is that it can facilitate thinking about the respective roles of courts and legislatures throughout much of the law.7 It also travels well and is increasingly the focus of attention in many parts of the world that seek to build on the traditions of common law, or what some call Commonwealth constitutionalism.8 The dialogue metaphor illuminates * FacultyofLaw,UniversityofToronto. 1 Christopher Manfredi, ‘The Life of a Metaphor: Dialogue in the Supreme Court, 1998–2003’(2004)23SupremeCourtL.Rev.(2d)105at112[Manfredi,‘Metaphor’]. 2 Mv.H,[1999]2S.C.R.3.;R.v.Hall,[2002]3S.C.R.309;Vriendv.Alberta,[1998] 1 S.C.R.493. 3 Little Sisters Book Emporium v. Canada (Minister of Justice), [2000] 2 S.C.R. 1120 [Little Sisters];DoucetBoudreauv.NovaScotia,[2003]3S.C.R.3. 4 Vriend,supranote2. 5 R.v.Mills,[1999]3S.C.R.668. 6 BellExpressVuPartnershipv.Rex,[2002]2S.C.R.559[BellExpressVu]. 7 Formyargumentsthatthedialoguemetaphorcasecanassistinunderstandingsome forms of common and international law see Kent Roach, ‘Common Law Bills of Rights as Dialogue between Courts and Legislatures’ (2005) 55 U.T.L.J. 733 [Roach, ‘Bills of Rights’]; Kent Roach,‘Constitutional, Remedial andInternational Dialogues aboutRights:TheCanadianExperience’(2005)40Tex.Int’lL.J.537. 8 StephenGardbaum,‘TheNewCommonwealthModelofConstitutionalism’(2001)49 Am.J.Comp.L.7071;AharonBarak,‘AJudgeonJudging:TheRoleofaSupremeCourt in a Democracy’ (2002) 116 Harv.L.Rev. 16 at 133–6 [Barak, ‘Judge on Judging’]; (2007),57UNIVERSITYOFTORONTOLAWJOURNAL 450 UNIVERSITYOFTORONTOLAWJOURNAL therelationbetweencourtsandlegislaturesinanycommonlawsystemin which legislatures can reply to the rights-protection decisions of courts and under any bill of rights that leaves space for legislatures to justify limits or derogations from rights. Atthesametime,themetaphorofjudicialreviewasaformofdialogue between courts and legislatures is controversial. There have been two main forms of criticism. One is that actual dialogue does not, in fact, occur very often between courts and legislatures; instead, what courts and commentators call a dialogue is more often a monologue.9 A second form of criticism is that the dialogue metaphor does not justify the role that courts play in the dialogue.10 In this essay, I will deal only with this second critique, arguing that in Justice Iacobucci’s hands, dialogue had a substantive and principled core. Justice Iacobucci engaged in a dialogue of principle in the sense that he brought questions of principle, rights, and the protection of vulner- able minorities to bear on his development of the common law, the interpretation of statutes, and his Charter jurisprudence while recogniz- ing that the legislature also retains the option of justifying limits or even overriding such principles altogether. In this sense, much of the substantive core of institutional dialogue about the place of principle in governance can be found in the important work of Alexander Bickel. I willalsoarguethat,forJusticeIacobucci,judicialreviewwaspartofaprin- cipled dialogue in the sense that the dialogue should be conducted in a fair and open manner that respects the distinct roles and abilities of Aharon Barak, The Judge in a Democracy (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2006) at 236–40 [Barak, Judge]; T.R.S. Allan, ‘Constitutional Dialogue and the Justification for Judicial Review’ (2003) 23 Oxford J.Legal Stud. 563; Richard Clayton, ‘Judicial Deference and “Democratic Dialogue”: The Legitimacy of Judicial Intervention under the Human Rights Act’ [2004] Pub.L. 33; Leighton McDonald, ‘Rights, “Dialogue” and Democratic Objections to Judicial Review’ (2004) 32 Fed.L.Rev. 1; Tom Hickman, ‘Constitutional Dialogue, Constitutional Theories and the Human Rights Act, 1998’ [2005] Pub.L. 306; Christine Bateup, ‘The Dialogic Promise: Assessing the Normative Potential of Theories of Constitutional Dialogue’ (2006) 71 Brooklyn L.Rev. 1109. For an excellent review of the Canadian literature on dialogue see Peter Hogg, Allison Bushell Thornton, & Wade Wright, ‘Charter Dialogue Revisited’ (2007) 45 Osgoode Hall L.J. [forthcoming] [Hogg et al., ‘DialogueRevisited’]. 9 MarkTushnet,‘JudicialActivismorRestraintinaSection33World’(2003)53U.T.L.J. 89;ChristopherManfredi&JamesKelly,‘SixDegreesofDialogue’(1999)37Osgoode HallL.J.513. 10 Andrew Petter, ‘Twenty Years of Charter Justification: From Liberalism to Dubious Dialogue’ (2003) 52 U.N.B.L.J. 187; Keith Ewing, ‘Human Rights’ in Peter Cane & Mark Tushnet, eds., The Oxford Handbook of Legal Studies (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003) 306; Alan Hutchinson, ‘Judges and Politics: An Essay from Canada’ (2005) 23 Legal Stud. 464; Luc Tremblay, ‘The Legitimacy of Judicial Review: The LimitsofDialogueBetweenCourtsandLegislatures’(2005)3Int’lJ.Const.L.617. ADIALOGUEABOUTPRINCIPLEANDAPRINCIPLEDDIALOGUE 451 courts,legislatures,andtheexecutive.Inthissense,muchofthesubstan- tive core of principled dialogue can be found in the important work of Lon Fuller. II The intellectual and substantive origins of dialogue theory JusticeIacobucci’sfirstexplicitdiscussionofdialoguebetweencourtsand legislatures was in Vriend v. Alberta,11 where he prefaced his decision to ‘read in’ sexual orientation as a prohibited ground of discrimination in Alberta’shuman-rightscodewithageneraldiscussionoftherelationship between courts and legislatures under the Charter. In that discussion he cited the famous article on dialogue written by Peter Hogg and Allison Bushell12 a year earlier, stating that theCharterhasgivenrisetoamoredynamicinteractionamongthebranchesof governance. This interaction has been aptly described as a ‘dialogue’ by some (see e.g. Hogg and Bushell, supra). In reviewing legislative enactments and executive decisionsto ensure constitutional validity, the courts speak to the leg- islativeandexecutivebranches.Ashasbeenpointedout,mostofthelegislation held not to pass constitutional muster has been followed by new legislation designed to accomplish similar objectives (see Hogg and Bushell, supra, at p.82). By doingthis, the legislature respondstothe courts; hence the dialogue among the branches. To my mind, a great value of judicial review and this dialogue among the branches is that each of the branches is made somewhat accountable to the other. The work of the legislature is reviewed by the courts and the work of the court in its decisions can be reacted to by the legislature in the passing of newlegislation(orevenoverarchinglawsunders.33oftheCharter).Thisdialo- guebetweenandaccountabilityofeachofthebrancheshavetheeffectofenhan- cing the democratic process, not denying it.13 In his discussion in Vriend, Justice Iacobucci recognized a need to respond to what Bickel had described as the ‘counter-majoritarian diffi- culty’ of unelected judges’ striking down democratically enacted laws. In Vriend, Justice Iacobucci described Bickel’s The Least Dangerous Branch: The Supreme Court at the Bar of Politics as an ‘outstanding work.’14 Bickel developed a nuanced and sophisticated theory of judicial review under the American Bill of Rights as a form of dialogue between the court and both legislatures and society. Bickel wrote about how many 11 Supranote2. 12 PeterHogg&AllisonBushell,‘TheCharterDialogueBetweenCourtsandLegislatures’ (1997)35OsgoodeHallL.J.75. 13 Vriend,supranote2atparas.138–9. 14 Ibid.atpara.133. 452 UNIVERSITYOFTORONTOLAWJOURNAL Supreme Court decisions ‘are the beginnings of conversations between the Court and the people and their representatives’15 and about how the Court ‘interacts with other institutions, with whom it is engaged in anendlesslyrenewededucationconversation...Anditisaconversation, notamonologue.’16Bickelwaswellawarethat,undertheAmericanBillof Rights, ‘the Court has the edge’17 in the dialogue, but much of his work encouragedthecourttominimizefull-blownconstitutionaldecisionsand insteadtouseavarietyofsub-constitutionaldevices,suchaspresumptions of statutory intent and the creative use of delay, to engage ‘in a Socratic colloquy with the other institutions of government and with society as a whole concerning the necessity for this or that measure, for this or that compromise.’18 In other words, Bickel struggled, within the confines of the American Bill of Rights, to find functional equivalents to ss. 1 and 33 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and suspended remedies. Bickel isafounderofamodern19theoryofdialogue betweencourtsandlegisla- tures, and it is significant that Justice Iacobucci cited Bickel in introdu- cing the theory of dialogue to Charter jurisprudence. Bickel also had a substantive approach to judicial review in that he argued that courts can, in appropriate cases, act on principles of fairness and non-discrimi- nation that the executive and legislatures are inclined to neglect. Bickel defended Brown v. Board of Education, but he also recognized the ability of legislatures and society to resist that just decision. Building on the work of Bickel, Guido Calabresi argued in 1991 that the Canadian Charter is ‘Bickellian’ in its promotion of dialogue between courts and legislatures.20 Calabresi’s observations were part of a larger argument that American constitutionalism had been dominated 15 Alexander Bickel, The Supreme Court and the Idea of Progress (New Haven, CT: Yale UniversityPress,1970)at91[Bickel,Progress]. 16 AlexanderBickel,TheMoralityofConsent(NewHaven,CT:YaleUniversityPress,1974) at111. 17 Bickel,Progress,supranote15at91. 18 AlexanderBickel,TheLeastDangerousBranch:TheSupremeCourtattheBarofPolitics,2d ed. (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1985) at 70–1 [Bickel, Least Dangerous Branch]. 19 BeforeBickel,ThomasJefferson,JamesMadison,andAndrewJacksonallappealedto the strong dialogic ideathat the elected branches of government could act on their interpretations even when they departed from the Court’s interpretation. For a contemporary defence of this form of coordinate construction see Mark Tushnet, Taking the Constitution Away from the Courts (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1999). 20 Guido Calabresi, ‘Foreword: Antidiscrimination and Constitutional Accountability (What the Bork Brennan Debate Avoids)’ (1991) 105 Harv.L.Rev. 80 at 124. Cass Sunsteinisanotherscholar who,inspiredbyBickel,hasarguedforconstitutionalism minimalism as a device to allow increased dialogue between courts and legislatures under the American Bill of Rights. See Cass Sunstein, One Case at a Time (Cambridge,MA:HarvardUniversityPress,1999). ADIALOGUEABOUTPRINCIPLEANDAPRINCIPLEDDIALOGUE 453 bytheextremesofjudicialorlegislativesupremacy.InspiredbyBickel,as well as by Paul Weiler’s defence of the override as an alternative to legis- lative or judicial supremacy,21 Calabresi argued that there should be increasedinterestinmiddle-groundpositionsinwhichcourtsrequireleg- islatures to justify and, if necessary, reconsider their policy objectives in lightofconcernsabouttheeffectsoflegislationonvulnerableminorities and legal principles. Judicial review, for Calabresi, should be focused on protecting ‘society’s outcasts’ and on ensuring that legislatures do not hide but, rather, justify their attempts to limit a broader range of rights. Calabresi’s concerns about anti-discrimination and constitutional accountability well capture the essence of Justice Iacobucci’s comments in Vriend. BothBickel’sandCalabresi’swritingsonjudicialreviewemergedfrom the legal process tradition of legal scholarship. This tradition is some- times associated with a simple and stark separation of powers between courts and legislatures and a positivistic view of law.22 Writing in the late 1950s, and without regard to developments such as Brown v. Board of Education, Henry Hart and Albert Sacks somewhat complacently argued for a principle of institutional settlement whereby ‘a decision which is the duly arrived at result of a duly established procedure’ ought ‘to be accepted as binding upon the whole society unless and until it has been duly changed.’23 In the 1960s and 1970s, however, the legal process evolved as scholars began to ask questions about whether all groups in society were included in the ‘duly established procedures.’ Some of the most important and enduring work that emerged from the legal process era was Bickel’s theory of judicial review, Lon Fuller’s theory of the ‘internal morality’ of law24 and John Hart Ely’s theory25 that robust judicial protection of minorities can be justified on process grounds. Both Bickel and Fuller contemplated a principled dialogue that rejected the positivist elements of the legal process tradition, and both sawcourtsashavinganimportantanddistinctroleindemocraticgovern- ance. For Bickel, the courts must fulfil a function that ‘differs from the 21 PaulWeiler,‘RightsandJudgesinaDemocracy’(1984)18U.Mich.J.L.Ref.51. 22 SeeWilliamEskridge&PhilipFrickey,‘AnHistoricalandCriticalIntroductiontothe LegalProcess’inHenryHart&AlbertSacks,TheLegalProcess(NewYork:Foundation Press,1994)li.SeealsoKentRoach,‘WhatIsNewandOldabouttheLegalProcess?’ (1997)47U.T.L.J.363. 23 HenryHart&AlbertSacks,TheLegalProcess(NewYork:FoundationPress,1994)at5. 24 LonFuller,TheMoralityofLaw,rev.ed.(NewHaven,CT:YaleUniversityPress,1969). Forarecognition of therelevance ofFuller’stheoryto dialoguebetween courts and legislatures see Mary Liston, ‘Willis, “Theology” and Rule of Law’ (2005) 55 U.T.L.J. 767at785. 25 JohnHartEly,DemocracyandDistrust(Cambridge,MA:HarvardUniversityPress,1980). 454 UNIVERSITYOFTORONTOLAWJOURNAL legislative and executive functions; which is peculiarly suited to the capabilities of the courts; which will not likely be performed elsewhere if the courts do not assume it.’26 Courts would participate in a dialogue by bringing points of principle to the attention of governments andthepeople.Bickelbelievedthatnogoodsocietycanlivewithoutprin- ciplesbutalsothatnofunctioningsocietycanfunctionsolelyonthebasis of principle. The dialogue between courts and the elected branches of government is the means to reconcile these tensions. Fuller’sapproachtolawdifferedfromBickel’sinextendingtoalllawand notonlytotheroleofcourtsbutalsotothatoftheexecutiveandthelegis- lature.Atthesametime,however,theideaofdialoguebetweencourtsand other branches of government, and between individuals and courts, is implicitinFuller’s understanding of lawas acollective collaborative enter- prise.Inotherwords,Fullerstressednotsomuchthedialogueaboutprin- ciplepresentedbyBickelbut,rather,theideaofaprincipleddialoguethat wouldoccurbetweenindividuals,courts,bureaucrats,andthelegislature.In thejudicialarena,‘principleddialogue’meantthatthepartiesareguaran- teedarighttoparticipateandaddressargumentstothejudgeinawaynot guaranteedinthepoliticalarena.27Theparticipationofthepartiesincreases thelegitimacyofjudicialdecisions.Fuller’sideasaboutprincipleddialogue alsoapplytolegislaturesthroughhisargumentthatlegislatures,nolessthan courts,shouldbeinfluencedbytheinternalmoralityoflaw.Thismeansthat legislatures should rule through public, prospective, understandable, and general rules. A legislature that fails to rule in this way fails to make law. Finally, Fuller also extended his theory of law to the executive, stressing that there should be congruence between law and the administration of lawbytheexecutive.28 Fuller defined law as an ongoing ‘enterprise’ and a ‘complex, collaborative effort’29 that requires participation and nurturing from judges, legislators, bureaucrats, and citizens, as opposed to a positivistic ‘one-way projection of authority.’30 For Fuller, law and democracy was a neverending dialogue that will best be conducted if citizens, legislatures, administrators,andcourtsallrespectbasicproceduresoffairnessintheir interactions, in other words, if all involved in democratic governance conduct a principled form of dialogue.31 Some scholars inspired by Fuller have articulated the idea of a culture of justification of all public 26 Bickel,LeastDangerousBranch,supranote18at24. 27 LonFuller,‘TheFormsandLimitsofAdjudication’(1978)92Harv.L.Rev.353. 28 Fuller,MoralityofLaw,supranote24at39etseq. 29 Ibid.at134. 30 Ibid.at192. 31 Onthe connection between Fuller’sview oflawand therule oflaw see T.R.S. Allan, Constitutional Justice: A Liberal Theory of the Rule of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press,2001)atc.3. ADIALOGUEABOUTPRINCIPLEANDAPRINCIPLEDDIALOGUE 455 power32 that is consistent with the idea of dialogue in which individuals can require the state to justify limits on rights in terms of both legality and proportionality. Althoughafullintellectualbiographymustbelefttoothers,itislikely that Justice Iacobucci was influenced by legal process thought and perhaps even by Bickel and Fuller. He was educated in law in the early 1960s, during the height of the legal process influence on scholarship. Although he did not attend Harvard Law School, which was the centre of legal process, his wife Nancy did, and she studied with both Hart and Sacks. Iacobucci’s academic work in corporate law was concerned with legal process questions such as the basic structures of cooperation and legality in complex organizations.33 His subsequent experience as a very senior administrator, first at the University of Toronto and later in the federal government, made him keenly aware of the complexities of governance, the important role of fair process, and the reality of back- and-forth dialogue in any process of democratic governance. I would alsosuspectthat,asafirst-generationCanadian,JusticeIacobucciwassen- sitivetotheimportanceofprocessandofmoreinclusiveparticipationfor thosewhoarenot normally inpower.Healso hadanaspirational viewof lawas goalsto be pursued as opposed to rulesto be obeyed. By the time hebecameajudge,healreadyhadextensiveexperienceinboththeinsti- tutional and the human sides of governance. Thisshortdiscussionoftheintellectualandsubstantiveoriginsofdialo- gue theory has been designed to illustrate that dialogue theory did not emergefromnowhereandthatitisnotsimplyapositivestudyoftheinter- actions between courts and legislatures. Rather, dialogue theory emerges from a legal processtradition that defined a distinct role for the indepen- dent judiciary, with its commitment to fair adjudication, but situated that role in an ongoing collaborative enterprise of democratic governance involving legislatures, executives, and the people. Those who believe that dialogue between courts and legislatures is simply a debatable empirical proposition, or that it is devoid of any justification for the judicial role, should more carefully examine its intellectual origins. Dialogue theorists starting with Bickel and Fuller attempt to situate the judicial role in the context of both democratically enacted governments and the endless democratic quest to establish and re-establish the legitimacy of state power and the broadest consent of the governed. 32 David Dyzenhaus, ‘Law as Justification: Etienne Mureinik’s Conception of Legal Culture’ (1998) 14 S.Afr.J.Human Right 11. Foran argument inspired by Fuller that the rule of law binds the executive and the legislature as much as the courts, see David Dyzenhaus, The Constitution of Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). 33 FrankIacobucci,‘TheBusinessCorporationsAct’(1971)21U.T.L.J.416&643. 456 UNIVERSITYOFTORONTOLAWJOURNAL III Dialogue and the common law Dialogue betweencourtsandlegislaturesisnotaproductoftheCharter. It builds on longstanding traditions of development of the common law and judicial interpretation of statutes. Justice Iacobucci recognized that Parliament clearly can amend the common law when he stated in 1999 that ‘[i]f the common law were to be taken as establishing the only poss- ibleconstitutionalregime,thenwecouldnotspeakofadialoguewiththe legislature. Such a situation could only undermine rather than enhance democracy. Legislative change and the development of the common lawaredifferent.’34Courts,indevelopingthecommonlaw,arecommonly respondingtolegislativeinertia,whichcanbeseenasatacitdelegationof authority to the judiciary. This delegation of authority is revocable, however, because the legislature can always reclaim the field through the enactment of clear legislation. To my mind, this suggests that courts can be quite creative when developing the common law. Indeed, much of administrative law, evidence law, and criminal law have been built on the judicial creativity that thrives in the absence of legislative direction. If the judges become too creative for the legislature’s liking, the legislature can enact reply legislation; reply legislation, however, cannot simply undo common law. As Fuller reminds us, legislation should, except in extraordinary circumstances, be prospective and general, and this will mean that the Court’s application of the common lawwillgovernalready-decidedcases.ForJusticeIacobucci,thissuggested that courts should be quite cautious in developing the common law. Justice Iacobucci considered the judicial role in developing the common law in one of his first cases he decided on the Supreme Court. The case involved the question of whether the common law rule that a spouse is not a compellable witness should continue to apply in a case where the spouse was irreconcilably separated from the accused. Justice Iacobucci held for the Court that the common law rule should evolve in light of social and legal acceptance of divorce and the values of the Charter. He wrote, Togiveparamountcytothemarriagebondovertherightofindividualchoicein casesofirreconcilableseparationmayhavebeenappropriateinLordCoke’stime, whenawoman’slegalpersonalitywasincorporatedinthatofherhusbandonmar- riage, but it is inappropriate in the age of the Charter. As Wilson J. put it in R.v.Morgentaler,[1988]1S.C.R.30,atp.166,theCharterrequiresthatindividual choicesnot berestricted unnecessarily.35 34 Mills,supranote5atparas.57,60. 35 R.v.Salituro,[1991]3S.C.R.654at674. ADIALOGUEABOUTPRINCIPLEANDAPRINCIPLEDDIALOGUE 457 In so holding, Justice Iacobucci placed the development of the common lawintotheinstitutionalcontextofdialoguebetweenthecourtsandlegisla- tures.Hecarefullyconsidered,butultimatelydidnotaccept,theargument thatParliamenthadimplicitlyaffirmedtheoldcommonlawruleofspousal incompetencebymakingonlylimitedexceptionstothatruleinrelationto certainviolentandsexualcrimes.Thisdecisionrecognizedthespecialrole ofcourtsinadvancinguniversalprinciples,incontrasttolegislatures,which typically respond tospecificpolitical pressuressuch asdemandstoreform lawsconcerning spousal abuse andsexual assault.Heappealedtogeneral principles of free choice and autonomy to conclude that the separated spouse should be competent to testify in her ex-husband’s forgery trial, eventhoughforgerywasnotacrimethathadcommandedspecificattention from the legislature. Consistent with the dialogue model, the legislature couldalwaysreplywithnewlegislationaffirmingtheoldcommonlawrule ofspousalincompetence.Thefactthatthiswasnotdone,however,should beseenasevidencethattheCourt’sdecisionwasacceptabletothelegisla- ture and to society, given our evolving social and legal values. When the SupremeCourtdevelopsthecommonlaw,itisontrialbecausethelegisla- turecanrejectthepremisesofitsruling. Although Justice Iacobucci changed the common law in Salituro, he struck a note of caution about how far courts should be prepared to use the common law to achieve law reform. He defined the judicial role as making ‘incremental changes to the common law to bring legal rules into step with a changing society.’36 He also argued that the court has before it a single case; majorchanges in the law should be predi- catedonawiderviewofhowtherulewilloperateinthebroadgeneralityofcases. Moreover, the court may not be in a position to appreciate fully the economic and policy issues underlying the choice it is asked to make.... Finally, and perhapsmostimportantly,thereisthelong-establishedprinciplethatinaconsti- tutional democracy it is the legislature, as the elected branch of government, which should assume the major responsibility for law reform.37 These statements follow Fuller’s warnings that the bipolar structure of adjudication makes courts less adept at deciding multifaceted and poly- centric issues, especially those concerning the distribution of scarce resources.38 They also reflect an appreciation of what Bickel recognized as the counter-majoritarian difficulty inherent in unelected courts’ making law in a democracy. AlthoughJusticeIacobucci’snoteofcautionaboutthedevelopmentof the common law in Salituro reflects aspects of legal process thought, it 36 Ibid.at666. 37 Ibid.at668. 38 Fuller,‘FormsandLimits,’supranote27.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.